Schwarz–Ahlfors–Pick theorem: Difference between revisions
en>Jowa fan The previous version of the page actually described the Schwarz-Pick lemma; Ahlfors's version involves curvature. I'm not sure about the relevance of harmonic functions |
en>Yobot m WP:CHECKWIKI error fixes - Replaced endash with hyphen in sortkey per WP:MCSTJR using AWB (9100) |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
In [[physics]], the '''no-communication theorem''' is a [[no-go theorem]] from [[quantum information theory]], which states that, during measurement of an [[quantum entanglement|entangled quantum state]], it is not possible for one observer, making a measurement of a subsystem of the total state, to communicate information to another observer. The theorem is important because, in [[quantum mechanics]], [[quantum entanglement]] is an effect by which certain widely separated events can be correlated in ways that suggest the possibility of instantaneous communication. The no-communication theorem gives conditions under which such transfer of information between two observers is impossible. These results can be applied to understand the so-called paradoxes in [[quantum mechanics]], such as the [[EPR paradox]], or violations of [[local realism]] obtained in tests of [[Bell's theorem]]. In these experiments, the no-communication theorem shows that failure of local realism does not lead to what could be referred to as "spooky communication at a distance" (in analogy with Einstein's labeling of [[quantum entanglement]] as "spooky action at a distance"). | |||
In very rough terms, the theorem describes a situation that is analogous to two people, each with a radio receiver, listening to a common radio station: it is impossible for one of the listensers to use their radio receiver to send messages to the other listener. This analogy is imprecise, because quantum entanglement suggests that perhaps a message could have been conveyed; the theorem replies 'no, this is not possible'. | |||
== | ==Informal Overview== | ||
The no-communication theorem states that, within the context of quantum mechanics, it is not possible to transmit classical bits of information by means of carefully prepared [[mixed state (physics)|mixed]] or [[pure state]]s, whether [[entangled state|entangled]] or not. The theorem disallows all communication, not just faster-than-light communication, by means of shared quantum states. The theorem disallows not only the communication of whole bits, but even fractions of a bit. This is important to take note of, as there are many classical radio communications encoding techniques that can send arbitrarily small fractions of a bit across arbitrarily narrow, noisy [[communications channel]]s. In particular, one may imagine that there is some [[statistical ensemble (mathematical physics)|ensemble]] that can be prepared, with small portions of the ensemble communicating a fraction of a bit; this, too, is not possible. | |||
The theorem is built on the basic presumption that the laws of quantum mechanics hold. Similar theorems may or may not hold for other related theories,<ref>S. Popescu, D. Rohrlich (1997) "Causality and Nonlocality as Axioms for Quantum Mechanics", ''Proceedings of the Symposium on Causality and Locality in Modern Physics and Astronomy'' (York University, Toronto, 1997).</ref> such as [[hidden variable theory|hidden variable theories]]. The no-communication theorem is not meant to constrain other, non-quantum-mechanical theories. | |||
The basic assumption entering into the theorem is that a quantum-mechanical system is prepared in an initial state, and that this initial state is describable as a mixed or pure state in a [[Hilbert space]] ''H''. The system then evolves over time in such a way that there are two spatially distinct parts, ''A'' and ''B'', sent to two distinct observers, [[Alice and Bob]], who are free to perform quantum mechanical measurements on their portion of the total system (viz, A and B). The question is: is there any action that Alice can perform, that would be detectable by Bob? The theorem replies 'no'. | |||
An important assumption going into the theorem is that neither Alice nor Bob are allowed, in any way, to affect the preparation of the initial state. If Alice were allowed to take part in the preparation of the initial state, it would be trivially easy for her to encode a message into it; thus neither Alice nor Bob participate in the preparation of the initial state. The theorem does not require that the initial state be somehow 'random' or 'balanced' or 'uniform': indeed, a third party preparing the initial state could easily encode messages in it, received by Alice and Bob. Simply, the theorem states that, given some initial state, prepared in some way, there is no action that Alice can take that would be detectable by Bob. | |||
The proof proceeds by defining how the total Hilbert space ''H'' can be split into two parts, ''H''<sub>''A''</sub> and ''H''<sub>''B''</sub>, describing the subspaces accessible to Alice and Bob. The total state of the system is assumed to be described by a [[density matrix]] σ. This appears to be a reasonable assumption, as a density matrix is sufficient to describe both pure and mixed states in quantum mechanics. Another important part of the theorem is that measurement is performed by applying a generalized [[projection operator]] ''P'' to the state σ. This again is reasonable, as projection operators give the appropriate mathematical description of [[quantum measurement]]s. After a measurement by Alice, the state of the total system is said to have ''[[wave-function collapse|collapsed]]'' to a state ''P''(σ). | |||
The goal of the theorem is to prove that Bob cannot in any way distinguish the pre-measurement state σ from the post-measurement state ''P''(σ). This is accomplished mathematically by comparing the [[trace (linear algebra)|trace]] of σ and the trace of ''P''(σ), with the trace being taken over the subspace ''H''<sub>''A''</sub>. Since the trace is only over a subspace, it is technically called a [[partial trace]]. Key to this step is the assumption that the (partial) trace adequately summarizes the system from Bob's point of view. That is, everything that Bob has access to, or could ever have access to, measure, or detect, is completely described by a partial trace over ''H''<sub>A</sub> of the system σ. Again, this is a reasonable assumption, as it is a part of standard quantum mechanics. The fact that this trace never changes as Alice performs her measurements is the conclusion of the proof of the no-communication theorem. | |||
== | == Formulation == | ||
The proof of the theorem is commonly illustrated for the setup of [[Bell test]]s in which two observers [[Alice and Bob]] perform local observations on a common bipartite system, and uses the statistical machinery of quantum mechanics, namely [[density state]]s and [[quantum operation]]s.<ref>{{cite journal |authors=Peres, A. and Terno, D. |title=Quantum Information and Relativity Theory |journal=Rev. Mod. Phys. |volume=76 |pages=93–123 |year=2004 |arxiv=quant-ph/0212023|doi=10.1103/RevModPhys.76.93|bibcode = 2004RvMP...76...93P }}</ref> | |||
Alice and Bob perform measurements on system '''S''' whose underlying [[Hilbert space]] is | |||
= | :<math> H = H_A \otimes H_B. </math> | ||
It is also assumed that everything is finite dimensional to avoid convergence issues. The state of the composite system is given by a density operator on ''H''. Any [[density operator]] σ on ''H'' is a sum of the form: | |||
:<math> \sigma = \sum_i T_i \otimes S_i </math> | |||
where ''T<sub>i</sub>'' and ''S<sub>i</sub>'' are operators on ''H''<sub>''A''</sub> and ''H''<sub>''B''</sub>. For the following, it is not required to assume that ''T<sub>i</sub>'' and ''S<sub>i</sub>'' are state projection operators: ''i.e.'' they need not necessarily be non-negative, nor have a trace of one. That is, σ can have a definion somewhat broader than that of a density matrix; the theorem still holds. Note that the theorem holds trivially for [[separable state]]s. If the shared state σ is separable, it is clear that any local operation by Alice will leave Bob's system intact. Thus the point of the theorem is no communication can be achieved via a shared entangled state. | |||
Alice performs a local measurement on her subsystem. In general, this is described by a quantum operation, on the system state, of the following kind | |||
:<math> P(\sigma) = \sum_k (V_k \otimes I_{H_B})^* \ \sigma \ (V_k \otimes I_{H_B}), </math> | |||
where ''V''<sub>''k''</sub> are called [[completely positive map|Kraus matrices]] which satisfy | |||
:<math> \sum_k V_k V_k^* = I_{H_A}.</math> | |||
The term | |||
:<math>I_{H_B}</math> | |||
from the expression | |||
:<math>(V_k \otimes I_{H_B})</math> | |||
means that Alice's measurement apparatus does not interact with Bob's subsystem. | |||
Supposing the combined system is prepared in state σ and assuming, for purposes of argument, a non-relativistic situation, immediately (with no time delay) after Alice performs her measurement, the relative state of Bob's system is given by the [[partial trace]] of the overall state with respect to Alice's system. In symbols, the relative state of Bob's system after Alice's operation is | |||
:<math>\operatorname{tr}_{H_A}(P(\sigma))</math> | |||
where <math>\operatorname{tr}_{H_A}</math> is the partial trace mapping with respect to Alice's system. | |||
One can directly calculate this state: | |||
:<math> \operatorname{tr}_{H_A}(P(\sigma)) = \operatorname{tr}_{H_A} \left(\sum_k (V_k \otimes I_{H_B})^* \sigma (V_k \otimes I_{H_B} )\right) </math> | |||
::::<math> = \operatorname{tr}_{H_A} \left(\sum_k \sum_i V_k^* T_i V_k \otimes S_i \right)</math> | |||
:::: <math> = \sum_i \sum_k \operatorname{tr}(V_k^* T_i V_k) S_i </math> | |||
:::: <math> = \sum_i \sum_k \operatorname{tr}(T_i V_k V_k^*) S_i </math> | |||
:::: <math> = \sum_i \operatorname{tr}\left(T_i \sum_k V_k V_k^*\right) S_i </math> | |||
:::: <math> = \sum_i \operatorname{tr}(T_i) S_i </math> | |||
:::: <math> = \operatorname{tr}_{H_A}(\sigma). </math> | |||
From this it is argued that, statistically, Bob cannot tell the difference between what Alice did and a random measurement (or whether she did anything at all). | |||
== Some comments == | |||
*If the density operator <math>P(\sigma)</math> is allowed to evolve under the influence of non-local interactions between A and B, then the calculation in the proof no longer holds.<ref>{{cite conference |last1=Peacock |first1=K.A. |last2=Hepburn |first2=B. |title=Begging the Signaling Question: Quantum Signaling and the Dynamics of Multiparticle Systems |booktitle= Proceedings of the Meeting of the Society of Exact Philosophy |year= 1999 | url=http://arxiv.org/abs/quant-ph/9906036}}</ref> | |||
*The no-communication theorem thus says shared entanglement alone can not be used to transmit any information. Compare this with the [[no-teleportation theorem]], which states a [[classical information channel]] can not transmit quantum information. (By ''transmit'', we mean transmission with full fidelity.) However, [[quantum teleportation]] schemes utilize both resources to achieve what is impossible for either alone. | |||
* The no-communication theorem implies the [[no-cloning theorem]], which states that quantum states cannot be (perfectly) copied. That is, cloning is a sufficient condition for the communication of classical information to occur. To see this, suppose that quantum states could be cloned. Assume parts of a [[Maximally entangled state|maximally entangled]] [[Bell state]] are distributed to Alice and Bob. Alice could send bits to Bob in the following way: If Alice wishes to transmit a "0", she measures the spin of her electron in the '''z''' direction, collapsing Bob's state to either <math>|z+\rangle_B</math> or <math>|z-\rangle_B</math>. To transmit "1", Alice does nothing to her [[qubit]]. Bob creates many copies of his electron's state, and measures the spin of each copy in the '''z''' direction. Bob will know that Alice has transmitted a "0" if all his measurements will produce the same result; otherwise, his measurements will have outcomes <math>|z+\rangle_B</math> or <math>|z-\rangle_B</math> with equal probability. This would allow Alice and Bob to communicate classical bits between each other (possibly across [[space-like]] separations, violating [[causality]]). | |||
== Opposing Viewpoint == | |||
Theorem fails to take weak quantum measurement into account and needs to be updated to consider this case. | |||
{{Misleading|section}} | |||
The use of Tensor product (<math> H = H_A \otimes H_B. </math>) to simplify the description is deeply problematic according to: | |||
<ref> J.B. Kennedy (1995). "On the empirical foundations of the quantum no-signalling proofs". Philosophy of Science 62: 543–560. </ref> | |||
The sender and Alice and Bob should on the contrary be understood as 3 labs which cooperate closely. | |||
The proof is also based on another assumption: | |||
'… means that Alice's measurement apparatus does not interact with Bob's subsystem’. | |||
Let's look at a small analysis of part of a classic two-channel experiment that is often used to show entanglement: | |||
Alice and Bob measures the corresponding particles from pairs of quantum mechanically entangled photons - known as Bell-par. | |||
Alice's measurement apparatus is a polarizing beam splitter and photo detectors. | |||
Bob’s measurement apparatus also starts with a polarizing beam splitter. | |||
Let one setting of Alice's polarizing beam splitter makes a distribution at Bob's polarizing beam splitter as (10% -90%) for the part of the beam that is transmitted through Alice's splitter. The second part, similar to those which are reflected at Alice’s splitter, will create a distribution of (90 % - 10%). Then Bob receives a random mix of (10% - 90%) and (90% -10 %). | |||
Another setting of Alice’s measurement apparatus could give Bob a mix of (60% - 40%) and (40% - 60%). | |||
These are clear differences in Bob's system caused by changes at Alice's measurement apparatus - and many measurements of correlations between Alice and Bob have confirmed these differences. | |||
So one of the assumings the proof is based on is wrong - '''and therefore the proof is also wrong'''. | |||
The problem with the communication is in some way to measure these changes, entanglement predicts. But it will probably be resolved over time. | |||
== See also== | |||
* [[No-broadcast theorem]] | |||
* [[No-cloning theorem]] | |||
* [[No-deleting theorem]] | |||
* [[No-teleportation theorem]] | |||
== References == | |||
{{Reflist}} | |||
* Hall, M.J.W. ''Imprecise measurements and non-locality in quantum mechanics'', Phys. Lett. A (1987) 89-91 | |||
* [[Giancarlo Ghirardi|Ghirardi, G.C.]] et al. ''Experiments of the EPR Type Involving CP-Violation Do not Allow Faster-than-Light Communication between Distant Observers'', Europhys. Lett. 6 (1988) 95-100 | |||
* Florig, M. and Summers, S. J. ''On the statistical independence of algebras of observables'', J. Math. Phys. 38 (1997) 1318- 1328 | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:No-Communication Theorem}} | |||
[[Category:Quantum measurement]] | |||
[[Category:Quantum information science]] | |||
[[Category:Physics theorems]] | |||
[[Category:Statistical mechanics theorems]] |
Revision as of 10:33, 20 April 2013
In physics, the no-communication theorem is a no-go theorem from quantum information theory, which states that, during measurement of an entangled quantum state, it is not possible for one observer, making a measurement of a subsystem of the total state, to communicate information to another observer. The theorem is important because, in quantum mechanics, quantum entanglement is an effect by which certain widely separated events can be correlated in ways that suggest the possibility of instantaneous communication. The no-communication theorem gives conditions under which such transfer of information between two observers is impossible. These results can be applied to understand the so-called paradoxes in quantum mechanics, such as the EPR paradox, or violations of local realism obtained in tests of Bell's theorem. In these experiments, the no-communication theorem shows that failure of local realism does not lead to what could be referred to as "spooky communication at a distance" (in analogy with Einstein's labeling of quantum entanglement as "spooky action at a distance").
In very rough terms, the theorem describes a situation that is analogous to two people, each with a radio receiver, listening to a common radio station: it is impossible for one of the listensers to use their radio receiver to send messages to the other listener. This analogy is imprecise, because quantum entanglement suggests that perhaps a message could have been conveyed; the theorem replies 'no, this is not possible'.
Informal Overview
The no-communication theorem states that, within the context of quantum mechanics, it is not possible to transmit classical bits of information by means of carefully prepared mixed or pure states, whether entangled or not. The theorem disallows all communication, not just faster-than-light communication, by means of shared quantum states. The theorem disallows not only the communication of whole bits, but even fractions of a bit. This is important to take note of, as there are many classical radio communications encoding techniques that can send arbitrarily small fractions of a bit across arbitrarily narrow, noisy communications channels. In particular, one may imagine that there is some ensemble that can be prepared, with small portions of the ensemble communicating a fraction of a bit; this, too, is not possible.
The theorem is built on the basic presumption that the laws of quantum mechanics hold. Similar theorems may or may not hold for other related theories,[1] such as hidden variable theories. The no-communication theorem is not meant to constrain other, non-quantum-mechanical theories.
The basic assumption entering into the theorem is that a quantum-mechanical system is prepared in an initial state, and that this initial state is describable as a mixed or pure state in a Hilbert space H. The system then evolves over time in such a way that there are two spatially distinct parts, A and B, sent to two distinct observers, Alice and Bob, who are free to perform quantum mechanical measurements on their portion of the total system (viz, A and B). The question is: is there any action that Alice can perform, that would be detectable by Bob? The theorem replies 'no'.
An important assumption going into the theorem is that neither Alice nor Bob are allowed, in any way, to affect the preparation of the initial state. If Alice were allowed to take part in the preparation of the initial state, it would be trivially easy for her to encode a message into it; thus neither Alice nor Bob participate in the preparation of the initial state. The theorem does not require that the initial state be somehow 'random' or 'balanced' or 'uniform': indeed, a third party preparing the initial state could easily encode messages in it, received by Alice and Bob. Simply, the theorem states that, given some initial state, prepared in some way, there is no action that Alice can take that would be detectable by Bob.
The proof proceeds by defining how the total Hilbert space H can be split into two parts, HA and HB, describing the subspaces accessible to Alice and Bob. The total state of the system is assumed to be described by a density matrix σ. This appears to be a reasonable assumption, as a density matrix is sufficient to describe both pure and mixed states in quantum mechanics. Another important part of the theorem is that measurement is performed by applying a generalized projection operator P to the state σ. This again is reasonable, as projection operators give the appropriate mathematical description of quantum measurements. After a measurement by Alice, the state of the total system is said to have collapsed to a state P(σ).
The goal of the theorem is to prove that Bob cannot in any way distinguish the pre-measurement state σ from the post-measurement state P(σ). This is accomplished mathematically by comparing the trace of σ and the trace of P(σ), with the trace being taken over the subspace HA. Since the trace is only over a subspace, it is technically called a partial trace. Key to this step is the assumption that the (partial) trace adequately summarizes the system from Bob's point of view. That is, everything that Bob has access to, or could ever have access to, measure, or detect, is completely described by a partial trace over HA of the system σ. Again, this is a reasonable assumption, as it is a part of standard quantum mechanics. The fact that this trace never changes as Alice performs her measurements is the conclusion of the proof of the no-communication theorem.
Formulation
The proof of the theorem is commonly illustrated for the setup of Bell tests in which two observers Alice and Bob perform local observations on a common bipartite system, and uses the statistical machinery of quantum mechanics, namely density states and quantum operations.[2]
Alice and Bob perform measurements on system S whose underlying Hilbert space is
It is also assumed that everything is finite dimensional to avoid convergence issues. The state of the composite system is given by a density operator on H. Any density operator σ on H is a sum of the form:
where Ti and Si are operators on HA and HB. For the following, it is not required to assume that Ti and Si are state projection operators: i.e. they need not necessarily be non-negative, nor have a trace of one. That is, σ can have a definion somewhat broader than that of a density matrix; the theorem still holds. Note that the theorem holds trivially for separable states. If the shared state σ is separable, it is clear that any local operation by Alice will leave Bob's system intact. Thus the point of the theorem is no communication can be achieved via a shared entangled state.
Alice performs a local measurement on her subsystem. In general, this is described by a quantum operation, on the system state, of the following kind
where Vk are called Kraus matrices which satisfy
The term
from the expression
means that Alice's measurement apparatus does not interact with Bob's subsystem.
Supposing the combined system is prepared in state σ and assuming, for purposes of argument, a non-relativistic situation, immediately (with no time delay) after Alice performs her measurement, the relative state of Bob's system is given by the partial trace of the overall state with respect to Alice's system. In symbols, the relative state of Bob's system after Alice's operation is
where is the partial trace mapping with respect to Alice's system.
One can directly calculate this state:
From this it is argued that, statistically, Bob cannot tell the difference between what Alice did and a random measurement (or whether she did anything at all).
Some comments
- If the density operator is allowed to evolve under the influence of non-local interactions between A and B, then the calculation in the proof no longer holds.[3]
- The no-communication theorem thus says shared entanglement alone can not be used to transmit any information. Compare this with the no-teleportation theorem, which states a classical information channel can not transmit quantum information. (By transmit, we mean transmission with full fidelity.) However, quantum teleportation schemes utilize both resources to achieve what is impossible for either alone.
- The no-communication theorem implies the no-cloning theorem, which states that quantum states cannot be (perfectly) copied. That is, cloning is a sufficient condition for the communication of classical information to occur. To see this, suppose that quantum states could be cloned. Assume parts of a maximally entangled Bell state are distributed to Alice and Bob. Alice could send bits to Bob in the following way: If Alice wishes to transmit a "0", she measures the spin of her electron in the z direction, collapsing Bob's state to either or . To transmit "1", Alice does nothing to her qubit. Bob creates many copies of his electron's state, and measures the spin of each copy in the z direction. Bob will know that Alice has transmitted a "0" if all his measurements will produce the same result; otherwise, his measurements will have outcomes or with equal probability. This would allow Alice and Bob to communicate classical bits between each other (possibly across space-like separations, violating causality).
Opposing Viewpoint
Theorem fails to take weak quantum measurement into account and needs to be updated to consider this case.
The use of Tensor product () to simplify the description is deeply problematic according to: [4]
The sender and Alice and Bob should on the contrary be understood as 3 labs which cooperate closely.
The proof is also based on another assumption: '… means that Alice's measurement apparatus does not interact with Bob's subsystem’.
Let's look at a small analysis of part of a classic two-channel experiment that is often used to show entanglement:
Alice and Bob measures the corresponding particles from pairs of quantum mechanically entangled photons - known as Bell-par. Alice's measurement apparatus is a polarizing beam splitter and photo detectors. Bob’s measurement apparatus also starts with a polarizing beam splitter.
Let one setting of Alice's polarizing beam splitter makes a distribution at Bob's polarizing beam splitter as (10% -90%) for the part of the beam that is transmitted through Alice's splitter. The second part, similar to those which are reflected at Alice’s splitter, will create a distribution of (90 % - 10%). Then Bob receives a random mix of (10% - 90%) and (90% -10 %).
Another setting of Alice’s measurement apparatus could give Bob a mix of (60% - 40%) and (40% - 60%). These are clear differences in Bob's system caused by changes at Alice's measurement apparatus - and many measurements of correlations between Alice and Bob have confirmed these differences.
So one of the assumings the proof is based on is wrong - and therefore the proof is also wrong.
The problem with the communication is in some way to measure these changes, entanglement predicts. But it will probably be resolved over time.
See also
References
43 year old Petroleum Engineer Harry from Deep River, usually spends time with hobbies and interests like renting movies, property developers in singapore new condominium and vehicle racing. Constantly enjoys going to destinations like Camino Real de Tierra Adentro.
- Hall, M.J.W. Imprecise measurements and non-locality in quantum mechanics, Phys. Lett. A (1987) 89-91
- Ghirardi, G.C. et al. Experiments of the EPR Type Involving CP-Violation Do not Allow Faster-than-Light Communication between Distant Observers, Europhys. Lett. 6 (1988) 95-100
- Florig, M. and Summers, S. J. On the statistical independence of algebras of observables, J. Math. Phys. 38 (1997) 1318- 1328
- ↑ S. Popescu, D. Rohrlich (1997) "Causality and Nonlocality as Axioms for Quantum Mechanics", Proceedings of the Symposium on Causality and Locality in Modern Physics and Astronomy (York University, Toronto, 1997).
- ↑ One of the biggest reasons investing in a Singapore new launch is an effective things is as a result of it is doable to be lent massive quantities of money at very low interest rates that you should utilize to purchase it. Then, if property values continue to go up, then you'll get a really high return on funding (ROI). Simply make sure you purchase one of the higher properties, reminiscent of the ones at Fernvale the Riverbank or any Singapore landed property Get Earnings by means of Renting
In its statement, the singapore property listing - website link, government claimed that the majority citizens buying their first residence won't be hurt by the new measures. Some concessions can even be prolonged to chose teams of consumers, similar to married couples with a minimum of one Singaporean partner who are purchasing their second property so long as they intend to promote their first residential property. Lower the LTV limit on housing loans granted by monetary establishments regulated by MAS from 70% to 60% for property purchasers who are individuals with a number of outstanding housing loans on the time of the brand new housing purchase. Singapore Property Measures - 30 August 2010 The most popular seek for the number of bedrooms in Singapore is 4, followed by 2 and three. Lush Acres EC @ Sengkang
Discover out more about real estate funding in the area, together with info on international funding incentives and property possession. Many Singaporeans have been investing in property across the causeway in recent years, attracted by comparatively low prices. However, those who need to exit their investments quickly are likely to face significant challenges when trying to sell their property – and could finally be stuck with a property they can't sell. Career improvement programmes, in-house valuation, auctions and administrative help, venture advertising and marketing, skilled talks and traisning are continuously planned for the sales associates to help them obtain better outcomes for his or her shoppers while at Knight Frank Singapore. No change Present Rules
Extending the tax exemption would help. The exemption, which may be as a lot as $2 million per family, covers individuals who negotiate a principal reduction on their existing mortgage, sell their house short (i.e., for lower than the excellent loans), or take part in a foreclosure course of. An extension of theexemption would seem like a common-sense means to assist stabilize the housing market, but the political turmoil around the fiscal-cliff negotiations means widespread sense could not win out. Home Minority Chief Nancy Pelosi (D-Calif.) believes that the mortgage relief provision will be on the table during the grand-cut price talks, in response to communications director Nadeam Elshami. Buying or promoting of blue mild bulbs is unlawful.
A vendor's stamp duty has been launched on industrial property for the primary time, at rates ranging from 5 per cent to 15 per cent. The Authorities might be trying to reassure the market that they aren't in opposition to foreigners and PRs investing in Singapore's property market. They imposed these measures because of extenuating components available in the market." The sale of new dual-key EC models will even be restricted to multi-generational households only. The models have two separate entrances, permitting grandparents, for example, to dwell separately. The vendor's stamp obligation takes effect right this moment and applies to industrial property and plots which might be offered inside three years of the date of buy. JLL named Best Performing Property Brand for second year running
The data offered is for normal info purposes only and isn't supposed to be personalised investment or monetary advice. Motley Fool Singapore contributor Stanley Lim would not personal shares in any corporations talked about. Singapore private home costs increased by 1.eight% within the fourth quarter of 2012, up from 0.6% within the earlier quarter. Resale prices of government-built HDB residences which are usually bought by Singaporeans, elevated by 2.5%, quarter on quarter, the quickest acquire in five quarters. And industrial property, prices are actually double the levels of three years ago. No withholding tax in the event you sell your property. All your local information regarding vital HDB policies, condominium launches, land growth, commercial property and more
There are various methods to go about discovering the precise property. Some local newspapers (together with the Straits Instances ) have categorised property sections and many local property brokers have websites. Now there are some specifics to consider when buying a 'new launch' rental. Intended use of the unit Every sale begins with 10 p.c low cost for finish of season sale; changes to 20 % discount storewide; follows by additional reduction of fiftyand ends with last discount of 70 % or extra. Typically there is even a warehouse sale or transferring out sale with huge mark-down of costs for stock clearance. Deborah Regulation from Expat Realtor shares her property market update, plus prime rental residences and houses at the moment available to lease Esparina EC @ Sengkang - ↑ 55 years old Systems Administrator Antony from Clarence Creek, really loves learning, PC Software and aerobics. Likes to travel and was inspired after making a journey to Historic Ensemble of the Potala Palace.
You can view that web-site... ccleaner free download - ↑ J.B. Kennedy (1995). "On the empirical foundations of the quantum no-signalling proofs". Philosophy of Science 62: 543–560.