Tachymeter (watch): Difference between revisions
en>Magioladitis m →Measuring speed: Remove invisible unicode control characters + other fixes using AWB (9871) |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
'''Self-verifying theories''' are consistent [[first-order logic|first-order]] systems of [[arithmetic]] much weaker than [[Peano arithmetic]] that are capable of proving their own [[consistency proof|consistency]]. [[Dan Willard]] was the first to investigate their properties, and he has described a family of such systems. According to [[Gödel's incompleteness theorem]], these systems cannot contain the theory of Peano arithmetic, and in fact, not even the weak fragment of [[Robinson arithmetic]]; nonetheless, they can contain strong theorems; for instance there are self-verifying systems capable of proving the consistency of Peano arithmetic. | |||
In outline, the key to Willard's construction of his system is to formalise enough of the [[Gödel]] machinery to talk about [[provability]] internally without being able to formalise [[Diagonal lemma|diagonalisation]]. Diagonalisation depends upon being able to prove that multiplication is a total function (and in the earlier versions of the result, addition also). Addition and multiplication are not function symbols of Willard's language; instead, subtraction and division are, with the addition and multiplication predicates being defined in terms of these. Here, one cannot prove the [[arithmetical hierarchy|<math>\Pi^0_2</math> sentence]] expressing totality of multiplication: | |||
:<math>(\forall x,y)\ (\exists z)\ {\rm multiply}(x,y,z).</math> | |||
where <math>{\rm multiply}</math> is the three-place predicate which stands for <math>z/y=x</math>. | |||
When the operations are expressed in this way, provability of a given sentence can be encoded as an arithmetic sentence describing termination of an [[analytic tableau]]. Provability of consistency can then simply be added as an axiom. The resulting system can be proven consistent by means of a [[relative consistency]] argument with respect to ordinary arithmetic. | |||
We can add any true <math>\Pi^0_1</math> sentence of arithmetic to the theory and still remain consistent. | |||
{{logic-stub}} | |||
==References== | |||
*Solovay, R., 1989. "Injecting Inconsistencies into Models of PA". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 44(1-2): 101—132. | |||
*Willard, D., 2001. "Self Verifying Axiom Systems, the Incompleteness Theorem and the Tangibility Reflection Principle". Journal of Symbolic Logic 66:536—596. | |||
*Willard, D., 2002. "How to Extend the Semantic Tableaux and Cut-Free Versions of the Second Incompleteness Theorem to Robinson's Arithmetic Q" . Journal of Symbolic Logic 67:465—496. | |||
==External links== | |||
* [http://www.cs.albany.edu/FacultyStaff/profiles/willard.htm Dan Willard's home page]. | |||
[[Category:Proof theory]] | |||
[[Category:Theories of deduction]] |
Revision as of 00:05, 18 January 2014
Self-verifying theories are consistent first-order systems of arithmetic much weaker than Peano arithmetic that are capable of proving their own consistency. Dan Willard was the first to investigate their properties, and he has described a family of such systems. According to Gödel's incompleteness theorem, these systems cannot contain the theory of Peano arithmetic, and in fact, not even the weak fragment of Robinson arithmetic; nonetheless, they can contain strong theorems; for instance there are self-verifying systems capable of proving the consistency of Peano arithmetic.
In outline, the key to Willard's construction of his system is to formalise enough of the Gödel machinery to talk about provability internally without being able to formalise diagonalisation. Diagonalisation depends upon being able to prove that multiplication is a total function (and in the earlier versions of the result, addition also). Addition and multiplication are not function symbols of Willard's language; instead, subtraction and division are, with the addition and multiplication predicates being defined in terms of these. Here, one cannot prove the sentence expressing totality of multiplication:
where is the three-place predicate which stands for . When the operations are expressed in this way, provability of a given sentence can be encoded as an arithmetic sentence describing termination of an analytic tableau. Provability of consistency can then simply be added as an axiom. The resulting system can be proven consistent by means of a relative consistency argument with respect to ordinary arithmetic.
We can add any true sentence of arithmetic to the theory and still remain consistent.
References
- Solovay, R., 1989. "Injecting Inconsistencies into Models of PA". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 44(1-2): 101—132.
- Willard, D., 2001. "Self Verifying Axiom Systems, the Incompleteness Theorem and the Tangibility Reflection Principle". Journal of Symbolic Logic 66:536—596.
- Willard, D., 2002. "How to Extend the Semantic Tableaux and Cut-Free Versions of the Second Incompleteness Theorem to Robinson's Arithmetic Q" . Journal of Symbolic Logic 67:465—496.