Shifted Gompertz distribution: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
No edit summary
 
en>BeyondNormality
Line 1: Line 1:
[http://www.taehyuna.net/xe/?document_srl=78721 free psychic] Andrew Berryhill is what his wife enjoys to call him and he totally digs that title. What me and my family members love is performing ballet but I've been taking on new things recently. Mississippi is the only location I've been residing in but I will have to move in a yr or two. Office supervising is exactly where her primary earnings arrives from.<br><br>My website: cheap [http://ltreme.com/index.php?do=/profile-127790/info/ accurate psychic readings] readings ([http://www.octionx.sinfauganda.co.ug/node/22469 just click the following article])
In [[mathematical logic]], a [[Theory (mathematical logic)|theory]]  is '''complete''' if it is a '''maximal consistent set''' of sentences, i.e., if it is [[consistency|consistent]], and none of its proper extensions is consistent. For theories in logics which contain [[classical logic|classical propositional logic]], this is equivalent to asking that for every [[sentence (mathematical logic)|sentence]] φ in the [[formal language|language]] of the theory it contains either φ itself or its negation ¬φ.
 
Recursively axiomatizable first-order theories that are rich enough to allow general mathematical reasoning to be formulated cannot be complete, as demonstrated by [[Gödel's incompleteness theorem]].
 
This sense of ''complete'' is distinct from the notion of a complete ''logic'', which asserts that for every theory that can be formulated in the logic, all semantically valid statements are provable theorems (for an appropriate sense of "semantically valid"). [[Gödel's completeness theorem]] is about this latter kind of completeness.
 
Complete theories are closed under a number of conditions internally modelling the [[T-schema]]:
*For a set <math>S\!</math>: <math>A \land B \in S</math> if and only if <math>A \in S</math> and <math>B \in S</math>,
*For a set <math>S\!</math>: <math>A \lor B \in S</math> if and only if <math>A \in S</math> or <math>B \in S</math>.
 
Maximal consistent sets are a fundamental tool in the [[model theory]] of [[classical logic]] and [[modal logic]]. Their existence in a given case is usually a straightforward consequence of [[Zorn's lemma]], based on the idea that a [[contradiction]] involves use of only finitely many premises. In the case of modal logics, the collection of maximal consistent sets extending a theory ''T'' (closed under the necessitation rule) can be given the structure of a [[Kripke semantics|model]] of ''T'', called the canonical model.
 
==Examples==
Some examples of complete theories are:
* [[Presburger arithmetic]]
* [[Tarski's axioms]] for [[Euclidean geometry]]
* The theory of [[dense linear order]]s
* The theory of [[algebraically closed field]]s of a given characteristic
* The theory of [[real closed field]]s
* Every [[Morley's categoricity theorem|uncountably categorical]] countable theory
* Every [[omega-categorical theory|countably categorical]] countable theory
 
==References==
{{Portal|Logic}}
* {{cite book |first=Elliott |last=Mendelson |title=Introduction to Mathematical Logic |edition=Fourth edition |year=1997 |publisher=Chapman & Hall |isbn=978-0-412-80830-2| pages=86}}
 
{{Logic}}
 
[[Category:Mathematical logic]]
[[Category:Model theory]]
 
 
{{mathlogic-stub}}

Revision as of 05:10, 10 December 2013

In mathematical logic, a theory is complete if it is a maximal consistent set of sentences, i.e., if it is consistent, and none of its proper extensions is consistent. For theories in logics which contain classical propositional logic, this is equivalent to asking that for every sentence φ in the language of the theory it contains either φ itself or its negation ¬φ.

Recursively axiomatizable first-order theories that are rich enough to allow general mathematical reasoning to be formulated cannot be complete, as demonstrated by Gödel's incompleteness theorem.

This sense of complete is distinct from the notion of a complete logic, which asserts that for every theory that can be formulated in the logic, all semantically valid statements are provable theorems (for an appropriate sense of "semantically valid"). Gödel's completeness theorem is about this latter kind of completeness.

Complete theories are closed under a number of conditions internally modelling the T-schema:

Maximal consistent sets are a fundamental tool in the model theory of classical logic and modal logic. Their existence in a given case is usually a straightforward consequence of Zorn's lemma, based on the idea that a contradiction involves use of only finitely many premises. In the case of modal logics, the collection of maximal consistent sets extending a theory T (closed under the necessitation rule) can be given the structure of a model of T, called the canonical model.

Examples

Some examples of complete theories are:

References

Sportspersons Hyslop from Nicolet, usually spends time with pastimes for example martial arts, property developers condominium in singapore singapore and hot rods. Maintains a trip site and has lots to write about after touring Gulf of Porto: Calanche of Piana.

  • 20 year-old Real Estate Agent Rusty from Saint-Paul, has hobbies and interests which includes monopoly, property developers in singapore and poker. Will soon undertake a contiki trip that may include going to the Lower Valley of the Omo.

    My blog: http://www.primaboinca.com/view_profile.php?userid=5889534

Template:Logic


Template:Mathlogic-stub