Joseph F. Traub: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Churn and change
 
en>Omnipaedista
enhance infobox
Line 1: Line 1:
Greetings. Let me start by telling you the author's name - Phebe. Supervising is my profession. Minnesota is where he's been living for years. Doing ceramics is what her family and her appreciate.<br><br>Look at my blog ... at home std test ([http://www.ubi-cation.com/ubication/node/6056 go to the website])
In [[linguistics|linguistic]] [[semantics]], a '''generalized quantifier''' is an expression that denotes a [[Property (philosophy)|property]] of a property, also called a [[higher-order]] property.  This is the standard semantics assigned to [[quantifier|quantified]] [[noun phrase]]s, also called [[determiner phrase]]s, or DP for short. In the example below, the DP ''every boy''  says of a property X that the [[set theory|set]] of entities that are ''boys'' is a [[subset]] of the set of entities that have property X. So the following sentence says that the set of boys is a subset of the set of sleepers.
::Every boy sleeps.
::<math>\{x\,|\, x \mbox{ is a boy}\} \subseteq \{x\,|\,x \mbox{ sleeps}\}</math>
 
This treatment of quantifiers has been essential in achieving a [[compositionality|compositional]] [[semantics]] for sentences containing quantifiers.<ref> Montague, Richard: 1974, '[http://www.blackwellpublishing.com/content/BPL_Images/Content_store/Sample_chapter/9780631215417/Portner.pdf The proper treatment of quantification in English]',
in R. Montague, Formal Philosophy, ed. by R. Thomason (New Haven). </ref><ref>Barwise, Jon and Robin Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. ''Linguistics and Philosophy'' 4: 159-219.</ref>
 
==Type theory==
A version of [[type theory]] is often used to make the semantics of different kinds of expressions explicit. The standard construction defines the set of types [[recursion|recursively]] as follows:
#''e'' and ''t'' are types.
#If ''a'' and ''b'' are both types, then so is <math>\langle a,b\rangle</math>
#Nothing is a type, except what can be constructed on the basis of lines 1 and 2 above.
 
Given this definition, we have the simple types ''e'' and ''t'', but also a [[countable]] [[infinity]] of complex types, some of which include:
::<math>\langle e,t\rangle;\qquad \langle t,t\rangle;\qquad \langle\langle e,t\rangle, t\rangle; \qquad\langle e,\langle e,t\rangle\rangle; \qquad \langle\langle e,t\rangle,\langle \langle e, t\rangle, t\rangle\rangle;\qquad \ldots</math>
 
*Expressions of type ''e'' denote elements of the [[universe of discourse]], the set of entities the discourse is about. This set is usually written as <math>D_e</math>.  Examples of type ''e'' expressions include ''John'' and ''he''.
*Expressions of type ''t'' denote a [[truth value]], usually rendered as the set<math>\{0,1\}</math>, where 0 stands for "false" and 1 stands for "true".  Examples of expressions that are sometimes said to be of type ''t'' are ''sentences'' or ''propositions''.
*Expressions of type <math>\langle e,t\rangle</math> denote [[Function (mathematics)|functions]] from the set of entities to the set of truth values. This set of functions is rendered as <math>D_t^{D_e}</math>. Such functions are [[Indicator function|characteristic functions]] of [[Set (mathematics)|sets]].  They map every individual that is an element of the set to "true", and everything else to "false."  It is common to say that they denote ''sets'' rather than characteristic functions, although, strictly speaking, the latter is more accurate. Examples of expressions of this type are [[predicate (grammar)|predicates]], [[noun]]s and some kinds of [[adjective]]s.
*In general, expressions of complex types <math>\langle a,b\rangle</math> denote functions from the set of entities of type <math>a</math> to the set of entities of type <math>b</math>, a construct we can write as follows: <math>D_b^{D_a}</math>.
 
We can now assign types to the words in our sentence above (Every boy sleeps) as follows.
**Type(boy)=<math>\langle e,t\rangle</math>
**Type(sleeps)=<math>\langle e,t\rangle</math>
**Type(every)= <math>\langle\langle e,t\rangle,\langle \langle e, t\rangle, t\rangle\rangle</math>
 
Thus, every denotes a function from a ''set'' to a function from a set to a truth value.  Put differently, it denotes a function from a set to a set of sets.  It is that function which for any two sets ''A,B'', ''every''(''A'')(''B'')= 1 if and only if <math>A\subseteq B</math>.
 
==Typed lambda calculus==
A useful way to write complex functions is the [[lambda calculus]]. For example, one can write the meaning of ''sleeps'' as the following lambda expression, which is a function from an individual ''x'' to the proposition that ''x sleeps''.
::<math>\lambda x. sleep'(x)</math>
Such lambda terms are functions whose domain is what precedes the period, and whose range are the type of thing that follows the period. If ''x'' is a variable that ranges over elements of <math>D_e</math>, then the following lambda term denotes the [[identity function]] on individuals:
::<math>\lambda x.x</math>
 
We can now write the meaning of ''every'' with the following lambda term, where ''X,Y'' are variables of type <math>\langle e,t\rangle</math>:
 
::<math>\lambda X.\lambda Y. X\subseteq Y</math>
 
If we abbreviate the meaning of ''boy'' and ''sleeps'' as "''B''" and "''S''", respectively, we have that the sentence ''every boy sleeps'' now means the following:
::<math>(\lambda X.\lambda Y. X\subseteq Y)(B)(S)</math> — [[Lambda calculus#β-reduction|β-reduction]]
::<math>(\lambda Y. B \subseteq Y)(S)</math> — β-reduction
::<math>B\subseteq S</math>
 
The expression ''every'' is a [[determiner (linguistics)|determiner]]. Combined with a [[noun]], it yields a ''generalized quantifier'' of type <math>\langle\langle e,t\rangle,t\rangle</math>.
 
==Properties==
===Monotonicity===
====Monotone increasing GQs====
A ''generalized quantifier'' GQ is said to be [[monotone increasing]], also called [[upward entailing]], just in case, for any two sets ''X'' and ''Y'' the following holds:
::if <math>X\subseteq Y</math>, then GQ(''X'') [[Entailment|entail]]s GQ(''Y'').
The GQ ''every boy'' is monotone increasing. For example, the set of things that ''run fast'' is a subset of the set of things that ''run''. Therefore, the first sentence below [[Entailment|entail]]s the second:
#Every boy runs fast.
#Every boy runs.
 
====Monotone decreasing GQs====
A GQ is said to be [[monotone decreasing]], also called [[downward entailing]] just in case, for any two sets ''X'' and ''Y'', the following holds:
::If <math>X\subseteq Y</math>, then GQ(''Y'') entails GQ(''X'').
An example of a monotone decreasing GQ is ''no boy''. For this GQ we have that the first sentence below entails the second.
#No boy runs.
#No boy runs fast.
The lambda term for the [[determiner (linguistics)|determiner]] ''no'' is the following. It says that the two sets have an empty [[Intersection (set theory)|intersection]].
::<math>\lambda X.\lambda Y. X\cap Y= \emptyset</math>
Monotone decreasing GQs are among the expressions that can license a [[negative polarity item]], such as ''any''. Monotone increasing GQs do not license negative polarity items.
#Good: No boy has '''any''' money.
#Bad: *Every boy has '''any''' money.
 
====Non-monotone GQs====
A GQ is said to be ''non-monotone'' if it is neither monotone increasing nor monotone decreasing. An example of such a GQ is ''exactly three boys''. Neither of the following two sentences entail the other.
#Exactly three students ran.
#Exactly three students ran fast.
The first sentence doesn't entail the second. The fact that the number of students that ran is exactly three doesn't entail that each of these students ''ran fast'', so the number of students that did that can be smaller than 3. Conversely, the second sentence doesn't entail the first.  The sentence ''exactly three students ran fast'' can be true, even though the number of students who merely ran (i.e. not so fast) is greater than 3.
 
The lambda term for the (complex) [[determiner (linguistics)|determiner]] ''exactly three'' is the following. It says that the [[cardinality]] of the [[Intersection (set theory)|intersection]] between the two sets equals 3.
::<math>\lambda X.\lambda Y. |X\cap Y|=3</math>
 
===Conservativity===
A determiner D is said to be ''conservative'' if the following equivalence holds:
::<math>D(A)(B)\leftrightarrow D(A)(A\cap B)</math>
For example, the following two sentences are equivalent.
#Every boy sleeps.
#Every boy is a boy who sleeps.
 
It has been proposed that ''all'' natural language determiners (i.e. in every language) are conservative (Barwise and Cooper 1981).  The expression ''only'' is not conservative. The following two sentences are not equivalent.  But it is, in fact not common to analyze ''only'' as a [[determiner (linguistics)|determiner]]. Rather, it is standardly treated as a [[focus-sensitive]] [[adverb]].
#Only boys sleep.
#Only boys are boys who sleep.
 
==See also==
*[[Lindström quantifier]]
*[[Branching quantifier]]
 
==References==
<references />
 
==Further reading==
* {{cite book|author1=Stanley Peters|author2=Dag Westerståhl|title=Quantifiers in language and logic|year=2006|publisher=Clarendon Press|isbn=978-0-19-929125-0}}
* {{cite book|author=Antonio Badia|title=Quantifiers in Action: Generalized Quantification in Query, Logical and Natural Languages|year=2009|publisher=Springer|isbn=978-0-387-09563-9}}
 
==External links==
*Dag Westerståhl, 2011. '[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/generalized-quantifiers/ Generalized Quantifiers]'.  [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]].
 
[[Category:Semantics]]
[[Category:Quantification]]

Revision as of 23:26, 11 December 2013

In linguistic semantics, a generalized quantifier is an expression that denotes a property of a property, also called a higher-order property. This is the standard semantics assigned to quantified noun phrases, also called determiner phrases, or DP for short. In the example below, the DP every boy says of a property X that the set of entities that are boys is a subset of the set of entities that have property X. So the following sentence says that the set of boys is a subset of the set of sleepers.

Every boy sleeps.

This treatment of quantifiers has been essential in achieving a compositional semantics for sentences containing quantifiers.[1][2]

Type theory

A version of type theory is often used to make the semantics of different kinds of expressions explicit. The standard construction defines the set of types recursively as follows:

  1. e and t are types.
  2. If a and b are both types, then so is
  3. Nothing is a type, except what can be constructed on the basis of lines 1 and 2 above.

Given this definition, we have the simple types e and t, but also a countable infinity of complex types, some of which include:

We can now assign types to the words in our sentence above (Every boy sleeps) as follows.

Thus, every denotes a function from a set to a function from a set to a truth value. Put differently, it denotes a function from a set to a set of sets. It is that function which for any two sets A,B, every(A)(B)= 1 if and only if .

Typed lambda calculus

A useful way to write complex functions is the lambda calculus. For example, one can write the meaning of sleeps as the following lambda expression, which is a function from an individual x to the proposition that x sleeps.

Such lambda terms are functions whose domain is what precedes the period, and whose range are the type of thing that follows the period. If x is a variable that ranges over elements of , then the following lambda term denotes the identity function on individuals:

We can now write the meaning of every with the following lambda term, where X,Y are variables of type :

If we abbreviate the meaning of boy and sleeps as "B" and "S", respectively, we have that the sentence every boy sleeps now means the following:

β-reduction
— β-reduction

The expression every is a determiner. Combined with a noun, it yields a generalized quantifier of type .

Properties

Monotonicity

Monotone increasing GQs

A generalized quantifier GQ is said to be monotone increasing, also called upward entailing, just in case, for any two sets X and Y the following holds:

if , then GQ(X) entails GQ(Y).

The GQ every boy is monotone increasing. For example, the set of things that run fast is a subset of the set of things that run. Therefore, the first sentence below entails the second:

  1. Every boy runs fast.
  2. Every boy runs.

Monotone decreasing GQs

A GQ is said to be monotone decreasing, also called downward entailing just in case, for any two sets X and Y, the following holds:

If , then GQ(Y) entails GQ(X).

An example of a monotone decreasing GQ is no boy. For this GQ we have that the first sentence below entails the second.

  1. No boy runs.
  2. No boy runs fast.

The lambda term for the determiner no is the following. It says that the two sets have an empty intersection.

Monotone decreasing GQs are among the expressions that can license a negative polarity item, such as any. Monotone increasing GQs do not license negative polarity items.

  1. Good: No boy has any money.
  2. Bad: *Every boy has any money.

Non-monotone GQs

A GQ is said to be non-monotone if it is neither monotone increasing nor monotone decreasing. An example of such a GQ is exactly three boys. Neither of the following two sentences entail the other.

  1. Exactly three students ran.
  2. Exactly three students ran fast.

The first sentence doesn't entail the second. The fact that the number of students that ran is exactly three doesn't entail that each of these students ran fast, so the number of students that did that can be smaller than 3. Conversely, the second sentence doesn't entail the first. The sentence exactly three students ran fast can be true, even though the number of students who merely ran (i.e. not so fast) is greater than 3.

The lambda term for the (complex) determiner exactly three is the following. It says that the cardinality of the intersection between the two sets equals 3.

Conservativity

A determiner D is said to be conservative if the following equivalence holds:

For example, the following two sentences are equivalent.

  1. Every boy sleeps.
  2. Every boy is a boy who sleeps.

It has been proposed that all natural language determiners (i.e. in every language) are conservative (Barwise and Cooper 1981). The expression only is not conservative. The following two sentences are not equivalent. But it is, in fact not common to analyze only as a determiner. Rather, it is standardly treated as a focus-sensitive adverb.

  1. Only boys sleep.
  2. Only boys are boys who sleep.

See also

References

  1. Montague, Richard: 1974, 'The proper treatment of quantification in English', in R. Montague, Formal Philosophy, ed. by R. Thomason (New Haven).
  2. Barwise, Jon and Robin Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 4: 159-219.

Further reading

  • 20 year-old Real Estate Agent Rusty from Saint-Paul, has hobbies and interests which includes monopoly, property developers in singapore and poker. Will soon undertake a contiki trip that may include going to the Lower Valley of the Omo.

    My blog: http://www.primaboinca.com/view_profile.php?userid=5889534
  • 20 year-old Real Estate Agent Rusty from Saint-Paul, has hobbies and interests which includes monopoly, property developers in singapore and poker. Will soon undertake a contiki trip that may include going to the Lower Valley of the Omo.

    My blog: http://www.primaboinca.com/view_profile.php?userid=5889534

External links