Ferroics: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>BattyBot
General fixes, removed orphan tag using AWB (7961)
 
en>Arbitrarily0
added internal links
Line 1: Line 1:
== Hollister Helsinki ==
In [[philosophical logic]], the concept of an '''impossible world''' (sometimes '''non-normal world''')
is used to model certain
phenomena that cannot be adequately handled using ordinary [[possible world]]s. An
impossible world, ''w'', is the same sort of thing as a possible world (whatever that may be),
except that it is in some sense "impossible." Depending on the context,
this may mean that some [[contradiction]]s are true at ''w'', that the normal laws of [[logic]] or of [[metaphysics]] fail to
hold at ''w'', or both.
==Applications==
===Non-normal modal logics===
Non-normal worlds were introduced by [[Saul Kripke]] in 1965 as a purely technical device to
provide semantics for [[modal logic]]s weaker than the system '''K''' — in particular, modal logics that reject
the rule of necessitation:


Se ei ollut stressiä; se oli viljaa hänen ruokavaliostaan ​​.. Joulukuuta lausuman (tukena Telangana valtion vireillepano), liittohallitus teki toisen julkilausuman 23. Kolmas tapaus ilmoitettiin tammikuun Se on jännittävää, siis tajuta, terveellinen tapa pois kaikki tämän pulman tavaksi taiteilija. <br><br>On usein hyödyllistä, että henkilö on tukiryhmä, joko epävirallisesti tai virallisesti. Jos erityisiä kansainvälistä humanitaarista oikeutta ei [http://www.geenius.eu/ Hollister Helsinki] tarkoita ilmasotaa ei kuulu sodan lakeja, vaan että ei ollut yleinen sopimus siitä, miten tulkita näitä lakeja. <br><br>Yli 450 erittäin interaktiivinen online simulaatioita laadut 3 [http://www.geenius.eu/ Hollister Eu] 12. Algerian suurlähettiläs Yhdysvalloissa: päällikkö Algerian pysyvä edustusto YK: 1982 84; Algerian suurlähettiläs, Paris 1979 82: Algerian suurlähettiläs, Bonn 1975 79: apulaispääsihteeri, Arabiliiton 1973 74: apulaispääsihteeri.. <br><br>Ei ole kulumista tai haketus materiaalista, ja se näyttää huomattavasti ammattimaisempaa. Minulla oli keskustella ihmisten kanssa, jotka uskovat valtavirran mediat mielikuvia naisista doesnt vaikuttaa naisten ja nuorten tyttöjen itsetuntoa. 276). Lähes jokaisessa talossa voisi käyttää [http://www.geenius.eu/ Hollister Tukholma] hieman jotain tehdä se sinun, ja useimmat yritykset hyötyisivät lisätä hieman koristeluun toimistoihin. <br><br>Silvan kaksi veljestä, hänen vanhempansa, ja hänen 90 vuotta vanha isoäiti liittyi häntä matkan joulukuussa, ja kaikki käyttivät perinteisiä Nigerian asuja. Me elämme elämäämme, tehdä mitä teemme, ja sitten nukumme. 'Minulla oli tapana olla vähän hullu, kun Ajoin, mutta ei enää', sanoi 53, joka ratsastaa Harley kotoaan Richmond San Franciscon keskustan viitenä päivänä viikossa ja säästää 30 minuuttia tunnissa radoittain jakaminen useimmat tavalla.. <br><br>Kaikki kesällä ei ollut halua; ja nyt alkoi tulla tallentaa ja linnut, kuten talvi lähestyi, josta tämä paikka teki runsaasti, kun he tulivat ensimmäistä (mutta myöhemmin laski astetta).. 'Annamme lisätietoja, kun pystymme tekemään niin.' Yhtiö sanoi palo oli onnettomuuden seurauksena eikä ollut spontaani event.The Tennessee Highway Patrol sanoi iltapäivällä tapaus sattui Interstate 24 Smyrna, kun sähköauton 'kesti vetokoukku' että 'osuma alavaunusta aiheuttajan sähkön aiheuttamat tulipalot.' Model S jousitus on [http://www.geenius.eu/ Hollister Suomi] panssarointi, joka suojaa litium-ioni-akku.. <br><br>Yhden outfielder pitäisi ainakin tienata klo lepakot korkeammalla tasolla nähdä, miten hän siirtyy, mutta toivottavasti yksi päivä baseball-fanit lukee hänen nimensä pienet League raportteja ja ei tarvitse kysyä, 'kuka?'. Minä rakastan sinua, 'ihan lokakuussa 1962 ..<ul>
: <math>\vdash A \Rightarrow \ \vdash \Box A</math>.
 
 
  <li>[http://frank1908.com/news/html/?206507.html http://frank1908.com/news/html/?206507.html]</li>
Such logics are typically referred to as "non-normal." Under the standard interpretation of modal vocabulary in [[Kripke semantics]], we have <math>\vdash A</math> if and only if in each model, <math>A</math> holds in all worlds. To construct a model in which <math>A</math> holds in all worlds but <math>\Box A</math> does not, we need either to interpret <math>\Box</math> in a non-standard manner (that is, we do not just consider the truth of <math>A</math> in every accessible world), or we reinterpret the condition for being ''valid''. This latter choice is what Kripke does. We single out a class of worlds as ''normal'', and we take ''validity'' to be truth in every normal world in a model. in this way we may construct a model in which <math>A</math> is true in every normal world, but in which <math>\Box A</math> is not. We need only ensure that this world (at which <math>\Box A</math> fails) have an accessible world which is not ''normal.'' Here, <math>A</math> can fail, and hence, at our original world, <math>\Box A</math> fails to be necessary, despite being a truth of the logic.
 
 
  <li>[http://lab.nqnwebs.com/lavoz_bak/spip.php?article15378/ http://lab.nqnwebs.com/lavoz_bak/spip.php?article15378/]</li>
These non-normal worlds are ''impossible'' in the sense that they are not constrained by what is true according to the logic. From the fact that <math>\vdash A</math>, it does not follow that <math>A</math> holds in a non-normal world.
 
 
  <li>[http://www.osvaldocarretta.it/node/68#comment-5788132 http://www.osvaldocarretta.it/node/68#comment-5788132]</li>
For more discussion of the interpretation of the language of modal logic in models with worlds, see the entries on [[modal logic]] and on [[Kripke semantics]].
 
 
  <li>[http://cups.reen-esports.de/index.php?site=guestbook http://cups.reen-esports.de/index.php?site=guestbook]</li>
===Avoiding Curry's Paradox===
 
[[Curry's Paradox]] is a serious problem for [[logician]]s who are interested in developing formal languages
</ul>
that are "semantically closed" (i.e. that can express their own semantics). The paradox relies on
the seemingly obvious principle of [[Idempotency of entailment|contraction]]:
 
:<math>(A \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B)) \rightarrow (A \rightarrow B)</math>.
 
There are ways of utilizing non-normal worlds in a semantical system that invalidate contraction. Moreover,
these methods can be given a reasonable philosophical justification by construing non-normal
worlds as worlds at which "the laws of logic fail."
 
===Counternecessary statements===
A counternecessary statement is a [[counterfactual conditional]] whose antecedent is not merely false, but ''necessarily'' so (or whose consequent is necessarily true).
 
For the sake of argument, assume that either (or both) of the following are the case:
 
:1. [[Intuitionism]] is false.
:2. The [[law of excluded middle]] is true.
 
Presumably each of these statements is such that if it is true (false), then it is [[logical truth|necessarily true]] (false).
 
Thus one (or both) of the following is being assumed:
 
:1′. Intuitionism is false at every possible world.
:2′. The law of excluded middle is true at every possible world.
 
Now consider the following:
 
:3. If intuitionism is true, then the law of excluded middle holds.
 
This is intuitively false, as one of the fundamental tenets of intuitionism is precisely that the LEM ''does not'' hold. Suppose this statement is cashed out as:
 
:3′. Every possible world at which intuitionism is true is a possible world at which the law of excluded middle holds true.
 
This holds vacuously, given either (1′) or (2′).
 
Now suppose impossible worlds are considered in addition to possible ones. It is
compatible with (1′) that there are ''impossible'' worlds at which intuitionism is true, and with (2′) that there are ''impossible'' worlds at which the LEM is false. This yields the interpretation:
 
: 3*. Every (possible or impossible) world at which intuitionism is true is a (possible or impossible) world at which the law of excluded middle holds.
 
This does not seem to be the case, for intuitively there are ''impossible'' worlds at which intuitionism is true and the law of excluded middle does not hold.
 
==Resources==
* Kripke, Saul. 1965. Semantical analysis of modal logic, II: non-normal modal propositional calculi. In J.W. Addison, L. Henkin, and A. Tarski, eds., ''The Theory of Models''. Amsterdam: North Holland.
* [[Graham Priest|Priest, Graham]] (ed.). 1997. ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic'' 38, no. 4. (Special issue on impossible worlds.) [http://projecteuclid.org/Dienst/UI/1.0/Journal?authority=euclid.ndjfl&amp;issue=1039540763 Table of contents]
* Priest, Graham. 2001. ''An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
 
==External links==
*{{sep entry|impossible-worlds|Impossible Worlds|Francesco Berto}}
* [[Edward N. Zalta]], [http://mally.stanford.edu/impossible.pdf A classically-based theory of impossible worlds] (PDF)
 
{{Logic}}
 
[[Category:Possible worlds]]
[[Category:Modal logic]]

Revision as of 21:24, 27 October 2013

In philosophical logic, the concept of an impossible world (sometimes non-normal world) is used to model certain phenomena that cannot be adequately handled using ordinary possible worlds. An impossible world, w, is the same sort of thing as a possible world (whatever that may be), except that it is in some sense "impossible." Depending on the context, this may mean that some contradictions are true at w, that the normal laws of logic or of metaphysics fail to hold at w, or both.

Applications

Non-normal modal logics

Non-normal worlds were introduced by Saul Kripke in 1965 as a purely technical device to provide semantics for modal logics weaker than the system K — in particular, modal logics that reject the rule of necessitation:

.

Such logics are typically referred to as "non-normal." Under the standard interpretation of modal vocabulary in Kripke semantics, we have if and only if in each model, holds in all worlds. To construct a model in which holds in all worlds but does not, we need either to interpret in a non-standard manner (that is, we do not just consider the truth of in every accessible world), or we reinterpret the condition for being valid. This latter choice is what Kripke does. We single out a class of worlds as normal, and we take validity to be truth in every normal world in a model. in this way we may construct a model in which is true in every normal world, but in which is not. We need only ensure that this world (at which fails) have an accessible world which is not normal. Here, can fail, and hence, at our original world, fails to be necessary, despite being a truth of the logic.

These non-normal worlds are impossible in the sense that they are not constrained by what is true according to the logic. From the fact that , it does not follow that holds in a non-normal world.

For more discussion of the interpretation of the language of modal logic in models with worlds, see the entries on modal logic and on Kripke semantics.

Avoiding Curry's Paradox

Curry's Paradox is a serious problem for logicians who are interested in developing formal languages that are "semantically closed" (i.e. that can express their own semantics). The paradox relies on the seemingly obvious principle of contraction:

.

There are ways of utilizing non-normal worlds in a semantical system that invalidate contraction. Moreover, these methods can be given a reasonable philosophical justification by construing non-normal worlds as worlds at which "the laws of logic fail."

Counternecessary statements

A counternecessary statement is a counterfactual conditional whose antecedent is not merely false, but necessarily so (or whose consequent is necessarily true).

For the sake of argument, assume that either (or both) of the following are the case:

1. Intuitionism is false.
2. The law of excluded middle is true.

Presumably each of these statements is such that if it is true (false), then it is necessarily true (false).

Thus one (or both) of the following is being assumed:

1′. Intuitionism is false at every possible world.
2′. The law of excluded middle is true at every possible world.

Now consider the following:

3. If intuitionism is true, then the law of excluded middle holds.

This is intuitively false, as one of the fundamental tenets of intuitionism is precisely that the LEM does not hold. Suppose this statement is cashed out as:

3′. Every possible world at which intuitionism is true is a possible world at which the law of excluded middle holds true.

This holds vacuously, given either (1′) or (2′).

Now suppose impossible worlds are considered in addition to possible ones. It is compatible with (1′) that there are impossible worlds at which intuitionism is true, and with (2′) that there are impossible worlds at which the LEM is false. This yields the interpretation:

3*. Every (possible or impossible) world at which intuitionism is true is a (possible or impossible) world at which the law of excluded middle holds.

This does not seem to be the case, for intuitively there are impossible worlds at which intuitionism is true and the law of excluded middle does not hold.

Resources

  • Kripke, Saul. 1965. Semantical analysis of modal logic, II: non-normal modal propositional calculi. In J.W. Addison, L. Henkin, and A. Tarski, eds., The Theory of Models. Amsterdam: North Holland.
  • Priest, Graham (ed.). 1997. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38, no. 4. (Special issue on impossible worlds.) Table of contents
  • Priest, Graham. 2001. An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

External links

Template:Logic