Tone mapping: Difference between revisions
en>Su-steve m →3) Local Contrast preservation: Improved spacing below Eqn 6. |
en>TiagoTiago m →Purpose and methods: i want more info about "gradient domain", so i made it a link in hopes someone will eventually write an article about it |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
The notion of '''institution''' has been created by [[Joseph Goguen]] and [[Rod Burstall]] in the late 1970s | |||
in order to deal with the "population explosion among the [[logical system]]s used in | |||
[[computer science]]". The notion tries to capture the essence of the concept of "logical system". | |||
With this, it is possible to develop concepts of [[specification language]]s (like structuring of specifications, parameterization, implementation, refinement, development), [[proof calculi]] and even [[tool]]s in a way completely independent of the underlying logical system. There are also [[morphism]]s that allow to relate and translate logical systems. Important applications of this are re-use of logical structure (also called borrowing), heterogeneous specification and combination of logics. Recently, [[institutional model theory]] has generalized many notions and deep results of [[model theory]]. | |||
==Definition== | |||
The theory of institutions does not assume anything about the nature of the logical system. That is, [[Interpretation (logic)|model]]s and [[Sentence (mathematical logic)|sentences]] may be arbitrary objects; the only assumption being that there is a '''satisfaction relation''' between models and sentences, telling whether a sentence holds in a model or not. Satisfaction is inspired by [[T-schema|Tarski's truth definition]], but can in fact be any binary relation. | |||
A crucial feature of institutions now is that models, sentences and their satisfaction are always being considered to live in some vocabulary or context (called '''signature''') that defines the (non-logical) symbols that may be used in sentences and that need to be interpreted in models. Moreover, '''signature morphisms''' allow to extend signatures, change notation etc. Nothing is assumed about signatures and signature morphisms except that signature morphisms can be composed; this amounts to having a | |||
[[Category (mathematics)|category]] of signatures and morphisms. Finally, it is assumed that signature morphisms lead to translations of sentences and models in a way that satisfaction is preserved. While sentences are translated along with signature morphisms (think of symbols being replaced along the morphism), models are translated (or better: reduced) '''against''' signature morphisms: for example, in case of a signature extension, a model of the (larger) target signature may be reduced to a model of the (smaller) source signature by just forgetting some components of the model. | |||
Formally, an institution consists of | |||
* a [[Category (mathematics)|category]] <math>Sign</math> of '''signatures''', | |||
* a [[functor]] <math>sen:Sign \to </math>[[Category of sets|Set]] giving, for each signature <math>\Sigma</math>, the set of '''sentences''' <math>sen(\Sigma)</math>, and for each signature morphism <math>\sigma:\Sigma\to\Sigma'</math>, the '''sentence translation map''' <math>sen(\sigma):sen(\Sigma)\to sen(\Sigma')</math>, where often <math>sen(\sigma)(\varphi)</math> is written as <math>\sigma(\varphi)</math>, | |||
* a [[functor]] <math>Mod:Sign^{op}\to</math>[[Category of small categories|Cat]] giving, for each signature <math>\Sigma</math>, the category of '''models''' <math>Mod(\Sigma)</math>, and for each signature morphism <math>\sigma:\Sigma\to\Sigma'</math>, the '''reduct functor''' <math>Mod(\sigma):Mod(\Sigma')\to Mod(\Sigma)</math>, where often <math>Mod(\sigma)(M')</math> is written as <math>M'|_{\sigma}</math>, | |||
* a satisfaction [[Binary relation|relation]] <math>{\models_{\Sigma}}\subseteq|{Mod(\Sigma)|\times sen(\Sigma)}</math> for each <math>\Sigma\in Sign</math>, | |||
such that for each <math>\sigma:\Sigma\to\Sigma'</math> in <math>Sign</math> the following '''satisfaction condition''' holds: | |||
<math>M'\models_{\Sigma'}\sigma(\varphi)</math> if and only if <math>M'|_{\sigma} | |||
\models_{\Sigma} \varphi</math> | |||
for each <math>M'\in Mod(\Sigma')</math> and <math>\varphi\in sen(\Sigma)</math>. | |||
The satisfaction condition expresses that truth is invariant under change of notation | |||
(and also under enlargement or quotienting of context). | |||
Strictly speaking, the model functor ends in the [[quasi-category]] of all large categories. | |||
==Examples of Institutions== | |||
* [[Propositional logic]] | |||
* [[First-order logic]] | |||
* [[Higher-order logic]] | |||
* [[Intuitionistic logic]] | |||
* [[Modal logic]] | |||
* [[Temporal logic]] | |||
* [[Web Ontology Language]] (OWL) | |||
* [[Common logic]] | |||
* [[Common Algebraic Specification Language]] (CASL) | |||
==Papers== | |||
* [[Joseph Goguen|J. A. Goguen]] and R. M. Burstall, Introducing Institutions, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 164, pp. 221–256, 1984. | |||
* J. A. Goguen and R. M. Burstall, Institutions: Abstract Model Theory for Specification and Programming, Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery 39, pp. 95–146, 1992. | |||
* J. Meseguer, General Logics, Logic Colloquium 87, pp. 275–329, North Holland, 1989. | |||
* J. A. Goguen and G. Rosu, Institution morphisms, Formal aspects of computing 13, pp. 274–307, 2002. | |||
* D. Sannella and A. Tarlecki, Specifications in an arbitrary institution, Information and Computation 76, pp. 165–210, 1988 | |||
* T. Mossakowski, J. A. Goguen, R. Diaconescu, A. Tarlecki. What is a Logic?. In Jean-Yves Beziau (Ed.), Logica Universalis, pp. 113–133. Birkhäuser 2005. | |||
==External links== | |||
*[http://www-cse.ucsd.edu/users/goguen/projs/inst.html Institutions by Joseph Goguen] | |||
*[http://www.informatik.uni-bremen.de/flirts/ Formalism, Logic, Institution - Relating, Translating and Structuring] (including large bibliography) | |||
*[http://www.imar.ro/~diacon/publications.html#Institutions__institution-independent Razvan Diaconescu's publication list] - contains recent work on institutional model theory | |||
==See also== | |||
* [[Entailment system]] | |||
* [[Abstract model theory]] | |||
* [[Institutional model theory]] | |||
[[Category:Theoretical computer science]] | |||
[[Category:Model theory]] |
Revision as of 10:01, 5 September 2013
The notion of institution has been created by Joseph Goguen and Rod Burstall in the late 1970s in order to deal with the "population explosion among the logical systems used in computer science". The notion tries to capture the essence of the concept of "logical system". With this, it is possible to develop concepts of specification languages (like structuring of specifications, parameterization, implementation, refinement, development), proof calculi and even tools in a way completely independent of the underlying logical system. There are also morphisms that allow to relate and translate logical systems. Important applications of this are re-use of logical structure (also called borrowing), heterogeneous specification and combination of logics. Recently, institutional model theory has generalized many notions and deep results of model theory.
Definition
The theory of institutions does not assume anything about the nature of the logical system. That is, models and sentences may be arbitrary objects; the only assumption being that there is a satisfaction relation between models and sentences, telling whether a sentence holds in a model or not. Satisfaction is inspired by Tarski's truth definition, but can in fact be any binary relation. A crucial feature of institutions now is that models, sentences and their satisfaction are always being considered to live in some vocabulary or context (called signature) that defines the (non-logical) symbols that may be used in sentences and that need to be interpreted in models. Moreover, signature morphisms allow to extend signatures, change notation etc. Nothing is assumed about signatures and signature morphisms except that signature morphisms can be composed; this amounts to having a category of signatures and morphisms. Finally, it is assumed that signature morphisms lead to translations of sentences and models in a way that satisfaction is preserved. While sentences are translated along with signature morphisms (think of symbols being replaced along the morphism), models are translated (or better: reduced) against signature morphisms: for example, in case of a signature extension, a model of the (larger) target signature may be reduced to a model of the (smaller) source signature by just forgetting some components of the model.
Formally, an institution consists of
- a category of signatures,
- a functor Set giving, for each signature , the set of sentences , and for each signature morphism , the sentence translation map , where often is written as ,
- a functor Cat giving, for each signature , the category of models , and for each signature morphism , the reduct functor , where often is written as ,
- a satisfaction relation for each ,
such that for each in the following satisfaction condition holds:
The satisfaction condition expresses that truth is invariant under change of notation (and also under enlargement or quotienting of context).
Strictly speaking, the model functor ends in the quasi-category of all large categories.
Examples of Institutions
- Propositional logic
- First-order logic
- Higher-order logic
- Intuitionistic logic
- Modal logic
- Temporal logic
- Web Ontology Language (OWL)
- Common logic
- Common Algebraic Specification Language (CASL)
Papers
- J. A. Goguen and R. M. Burstall, Introducing Institutions, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 164, pp. 221–256, 1984.
- J. A. Goguen and R. M. Burstall, Institutions: Abstract Model Theory for Specification and Programming, Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery 39, pp. 95–146, 1992.
- J. Meseguer, General Logics, Logic Colloquium 87, pp. 275–329, North Holland, 1989.
- J. A. Goguen and G. Rosu, Institution morphisms, Formal aspects of computing 13, pp. 274–307, 2002.
- D. Sannella and A. Tarlecki, Specifications in an arbitrary institution, Information and Computation 76, pp. 165–210, 1988
- T. Mossakowski, J. A. Goguen, R. Diaconescu, A. Tarlecki. What is a Logic?. In Jean-Yves Beziau (Ed.), Logica Universalis, pp. 113–133. Birkhäuser 2005.
External links
- Institutions by Joseph Goguen
- Formalism, Logic, Institution - Relating, Translating and Structuring (including large bibliography)
- Razvan Diaconescu's publication list - contains recent work on institutional model theory