Topological skeleton: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>EmausBot
m r2.7.2+) (Robot: Adding ca:Esquelet topològic
 
Line 1: Line 1:
I would like to introduce myself to you, I am Andrew and my spouse doesn't like it at all. Credit authorising is how he tends to make money. Mississippi is the only location I've been residing in but I will have to transfer in a year or two. As a woman what she truly likes is style and she's been performing it for quite a whilst.<br><br>my weblog; clairvoyance [[http://surimcons.com/port01/1986925 visit this site surimcons.com]]
In [[mathematical logic]], the '''Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation''', or '''BHK interpretation''', of [[intuitionistic logic]] was proposed by [[L. E. J. Brouwer]], [[Arend Heyting]] and independently by [[Andrey Kolmogorov]]. It is also sometimes called the '''realizability interpretation''', because of the connection with the [[realizability]] theory of [[Stephen Kleene]].
 
== The interpretation ==
 
The interpretation states exactly what is intended to be a proof of a given [[Formula (mathematical logic)|formula]]. This is specified by [[induction on the structure]] of that formula:
 
*A proof of <math>P \wedge Q</math> is a pair <''a'',&nbsp;''b''> where ''a'' is a proof of ''P'' and ''b'' is a proof of ''Q''.
*A proof of <math>P \vee Q</math> is a pair <''a'', ''b''> where ''a'' is 0 and ''b'' is a proof of ''P'', or ''a'' is 1 and ''b'' is a proof of ''Q''.
*A proof of <math>P \to Q</math> is a function ''f'' which converts a proof of ''P'' into a proof of ''Q''.
*A proof of <math>\exists x \in S : \phi(x)</math> is a pair <''a'', ''b''> where ''a'' is an element of ''S'', and ''b'' is a proof of ''φ(a)''.
*A proof of <math>\forall x \in S : \phi(x)</math> is a function ''f'' which converts an element ''a'' of ''S'' into a proof of ''φ(a)''.
*The formula <math>\neg P</math> is defined as <math>P \to \bot</math>, so a proof of it is a function ''f'' which converts a proof of ''P'' into a proof of <math>\bot</math>.
*There is no proof of <math>\bot</math> (the absurdity).
 
The interpretation of a primitive proposition is supposed to be known from context. In the context of arithmetic, a proof of the formula ''s''=''t'' is a computation reducing the two terms to the same numeral.
 
Kolmogorov followed the same lines but phrased his interpretation in terms of problems and solutions. To assert a formula is to claim to know a solution to the problem represented by that formula. For instance <math>P \to Q</math> is the problem of reducing ''Q'' to ''P''; to solve it requires a method to solve problem ''Q'' given a solution to problem&nbsp;''P''.
 
== Examples ==
 
The identity function is a proof of the formula <math>P \to P</math>, no matter what P is.
 
The [[law of non-contradiction]] <math>\neg (P \wedge \neg P)</math> expands to <math>(P \wedge (P \to \bot)) \to \bot</math>:
* A proof of <math>(P \wedge (P \to \bot)) \to \bot</math> is a function ''f'' which converts a proof of <math>(P \wedge (P \to \bot))</math> into a proof of <math>\bot</math>.
* A proof of <math>(P \wedge (P \to \bot))</math> is a pair of proofs <''a'',''b''>, where ''a'' is a proof of ''P'', and ''b'' is a proof of <math>P \to \bot</math>.
* A proof of <math>P \to \bot</math> is a function which converts a proof of ''P'' into a proof of <math>\bot</math>.
Putting it all together, a proof of <math>(P \wedge (P \to \bot)) \to \bot</math> is a function ''f'' which converts a pair <''a'',''b''> – where ''a'' is a proof of ''P'', and ''b'' is a function which converts a proof of ''P'' into a proof of <math>\bot</math> – into a proof of <math>\bot</math>.
The function <math>f(\langle a, b \rangle) = b(a)</math> fits the bill, proving the law of non-contradiction, no matter what P is.
 
On the other hand, the [[law of excluded middle]] <math>P \vee (\neg P)</math> expands to <math>P \vee (P \to \bot)</math>, and in general has no proof. According to the interpretation, a proof of <math>P \vee (\neg P)</math> is a pair <''a'',&nbsp;''b''> where ''a'' is 0 and ''b'' is a proof of ''P'', or ''a'' is 1 and ''b'' is a proof of <math>P \to \bot</math>. Thus if neither ''P'' nor <math>P \to \bot</math> is provable then neither is <math>P \vee (\neg P)</math>.
 
== What is absurdity? ==
 
It is not in general possible for a [[logical system]] to have a formal negation operator such that there is a proof of ''"not" P'' exactly when there isn't a proof of ''P'' ; see [[Gödel's incompleteness theorems]]. The BHK interpretation instead takes ''"not" P'' to mean that ''P'' leads to absurdity, designated <math>\bot</math>, so that a proof of ''&not;P'' is a function converting a proof of ''P'' into a proof of absurdity.
 
A standard example of absurdity is found in dealing with arithmetic. Assume that 0&nbsp;=&nbsp;1, and proceed by [[mathematical induction]]: 0&nbsp;=&nbsp;0 by the axiom of equality. Now (induction hypothesis), if 0 were equal to a certain natural number ''n'', then 1 would be equal to ''n''+1, ([[Peano arithmetic|Peano axiom]]: '''S'''''m''&nbsp;=&nbsp;'''S'''''n'' if and only if ''m'' = ''n''), but since 0=1, therefore 0 would also be equal to ''n''&nbsp;+&nbsp;1. By induction, 0 is equal to all numbers, and therefore any two natural numbers become equal.
 
Therefore, there is a way to go from a proof of 0=1 to a proof of any basic arithmetic equality, and thus to a proof of any complex arithmetic proposition. Furthermore, to get this result it was not necessary to invoke the Peano axiom which states that 0 is "not" the successor of any natural number. This makes 0=1 suitable as <math>\bot</math> in Heyting arithmetic (and the Peano axiom is rewritten 0&nbsp;=&nbsp;'''S'''''n'' &rarr; 0&nbsp;=&nbsp;'''S'''0). This use of 0&nbsp;=&nbsp;1 validates the [[principle of explosion]].
 
== What is a function? ==
 
The BHK interpretation will depend on the view taken about what constitutes a ''function'' which converts one proof to another, or which converts an element of a domain to a proof. Different versions of [[constructivism (mathematics)|constructivism]] will diverge on this point.
 
Kleene's realizability theory identifies the functions with the [[computable function]]s. It deals with [[Heyting arithmetic]], where the domain of quantification is the natural numbers and the primitive propositions are of the form x=y. A proof of x=y is simply the trivial algorithm if x evaluates to the same number that y does (which is always decidable for natural numbers), otherwise there is no proof. These are then built up by induction into more complex algorithms.
 
If one takes [[lambda calculus]] as defining the notion of a function, then the BHK interpretation describes the [[Curry&ndash;Howard correspondence|correspondence]] between natural deduction and functions.
 
== References ==
*{{cite paper |authorlink=A. S. Troelstra |last=Troelstra |first=A. |title=History of Constructivism in the Twentieth Century |year=1991 |url=http://staff.science.uva.nl/~anne/hhhist.pdf |doi= }}
*{{cite paper |last=Troelstra |first=A. |title=Constructivism and Proof Theory |year=2003 |url=http://staff.science.uva.nl/~anne/eolss.pdf |doi= }}
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov interpretation}}
[[Category:Dependently typed programming]]
[[Category:Functional programming]]
[[Category:Constructivism (mathematics)]]

Revision as of 08:55, 3 January 2014

In mathematical logic, the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, or BHK interpretation, of intuitionistic logic was proposed by L. E. J. Brouwer, Arend Heyting and independently by Andrey Kolmogorov. It is also sometimes called the realizability interpretation, because of the connection with the realizability theory of Stephen Kleene.

The interpretation

The interpretation states exactly what is intended to be a proof of a given formula. This is specified by induction on the structure of that formula:

The interpretation of a primitive proposition is supposed to be known from context. In the context of arithmetic, a proof of the formula s=t is a computation reducing the two terms to the same numeral.

Kolmogorov followed the same lines but phrased his interpretation in terms of problems and solutions. To assert a formula is to claim to know a solution to the problem represented by that formula. For instance is the problem of reducing Q to P; to solve it requires a method to solve problem Q given a solution to problem P.

Examples

The identity function is a proof of the formula , no matter what P is.

The law of non-contradiction expands to :

Putting it all together, a proof of is a function f which converts a pair <a,b> – where a is a proof of P, and b is a function which converts a proof of P into a proof of – into a proof of . The function fits the bill, proving the law of non-contradiction, no matter what P is.

On the other hand, the law of excluded middle expands to , and in general has no proof. According to the interpretation, a proof of is a pair <ab> where a is 0 and b is a proof of P, or a is 1 and b is a proof of . Thus if neither P nor is provable then neither is .

What is absurdity?

It is not in general possible for a logical system to have a formal negation operator such that there is a proof of "not" P exactly when there isn't a proof of P ; see Gödel's incompleteness theorems. The BHK interpretation instead takes "not" P to mean that P leads to absurdity, designated , so that a proof of ¬P is a function converting a proof of P into a proof of absurdity.

A standard example of absurdity is found in dealing with arithmetic. Assume that 0 = 1, and proceed by mathematical induction: 0 = 0 by the axiom of equality. Now (induction hypothesis), if 0 were equal to a certain natural number n, then 1 would be equal to n+1, (Peano axiom: Sm = Sn if and only if m = n), but since 0=1, therefore 0 would also be equal to n + 1. By induction, 0 is equal to all numbers, and therefore any two natural numbers become equal.

Therefore, there is a way to go from a proof of 0=1 to a proof of any basic arithmetic equality, and thus to a proof of any complex arithmetic proposition. Furthermore, to get this result it was not necessary to invoke the Peano axiom which states that 0 is "not" the successor of any natural number. This makes 0=1 suitable as in Heyting arithmetic (and the Peano axiom is rewritten 0 = Sn → 0 = S0). This use of 0 = 1 validates the principle of explosion.

What is a function?

The BHK interpretation will depend on the view taken about what constitutes a function which converts one proof to another, or which converts an element of a domain to a proof. Different versions of constructivism will diverge on this point.

Kleene's realizability theory identifies the functions with the computable functions. It deals with Heyting arithmetic, where the domain of quantification is the natural numbers and the primitive propositions are of the form x=y. A proof of x=y is simply the trivial algorithm if x evaluates to the same number that y does (which is always decidable for natural numbers), otherwise there is no proof. These are then built up by induction into more complex algorithms.

If one takes lambda calculus as defining the notion of a function, then the BHK interpretation describes the correspondence between natural deduction and functions.

References