Kilogram per cubic metre: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Addbot
m Bot: Migrating 24 interwiki links, now provided by Wikidata on d:q844211 (Report Errors)
en>Nclm
Illustration
 
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Cox's theorem''', named after the physicist [[Richard Threlkeld Cox]], is a derivation of the laws of [[probability theory]] from a certain set of [[postulates]]. This derivation justifies the so-called "logical" interpretation of probability. As the laws of probability derived by Cox's theorem are applicable to any proposition, logical probability is a type of [[Bayesian probability]]. Other forms of Bayesianism, such as the subjective interpretation, are given other justifications.
My name is Mаkayla and I am studying Nursing and Desіgn and Technology at Dallas / United States.  <br><br>Black and pink coach purses
 
==Cox's assumptions==
Cox wanted his system to satisfy the following conditions:
 
#Divisibility and comparability&nbsp;&ndash; The plausibility of a statement is a real number and is dependent on information we have related to the statement.
#Common sense&nbsp;&ndash; Plausibilities should vary sensibly with the assessment of plausibilities in the model.
#Consistency&nbsp;&ndash; If the plausibility of a statement can be derived in many ways, all the results must be equal.
 
The postulates as stated here are taken from Arnborg and Sjödin.<ref name="AS1999">Stefan Arnborg and Gunnar Sjödin, ''On the foundations of Bayesianism,'' Preprint: Nada, KTH (1999) &mdash; ftp://ftp.nada.kth.se/pub/documents/Theory/Stefan-Arnborg/06arnborg.ps &mdash; ftp://ftp.nada.kth.se/pub/documents/Theory/Stefan-Arnborg/06arnborg.pdf</ref><ref name="AS2000a">Stefan Arnborg and Gunnar Sjödin, ''A note on the foundations of Bayesianism,'' Preprint: Nada, KTH (2000a) &mdash; ftp://ftp.nada.kth.se/pub/documents/Theory/Stefan-Arnborg/fobshle.ps &mdash; ftp://ftp.nada.kth.se/pub/documents/Theory/Stefan-Arnborg/fobshle.pdf</ref><ref name="AS2000b">Stefan Arnborg and Gunnar Sjödin, "Bayes rules in finite models," in ''European Conference on Artificial Intelligence,'' Berlin, (2000b) &mdash; ftp://ftp.nada.kth.se/pub/documents/Theory/Stefan-Arnborg/fobc1.ps &mdash; ftp://ftp.nada.kth.se/pub/documents/Theory/Stefan-Arnborg/fobc1.pdf</ref>
"[[Common sense]]" includes consistency with Aristotelian [[logic]] when
statements are completely plausible or implausible.
 
The postulates as originally stated by Cox were not mathematically
rigorous (although better than the informal description above), e.g.,
as noted by Halpern.<ref name="H99a">Joseph Y. Halpern, "A counterexample to theorems of Cox and Fine," ''Journal of AI research,'' 10, 67&ndash;85 (1999) &mdash; http://www.cs.washington.edu/research/jair/abstracts/halpern99a.html</ref><ref name="H99b">Joseph Y. Halpern, "Technical Addendum, Cox's theorem Revisited," ''Journal of AI research,'' 11, 429&ndash;435 (1999) &mdash; http://www.cs.washington.edu/research/jair/abstracts/halpern99b.html</ref>  However it appears to be possible
to augment them with various mathematical assumptions made either
implicitly or explicitly by Cox to produce a valid proof.
 
Cox's axioms and functional equations are:
 
*The plausibility of a proposition determines the plausibility of the proposition's negation; either decreases as the other increases.  Because "a double negative is an affirmative", this becomes a functional equation
 
::<math>f(f(x))=x,\,</math>
 
:saying that the function ''f'' that maps the probability of a proposition to the probability of the proposition's negation is an [[Involution_(mathematics)#Involutions_in_mathematical_logic|involution]], i.e., it is its own inverse.
 
*The plausibility of the conjunction [''A'' & ''B''] of two propositions ''A'', ''B'', depends only on the plausibility of ''B'' and that of ''A'' '''''given''''' that ''B'' is true. (From this Cox eventually infers that conjunction of plausibilities is associative, and then that it may as well be ordinary multiplication of real numbers.)  Because of the associative nature of the "and" operation in propositional logic, this becomes a functional equation saying that the function ''g'' such that
 
::<math>P(A\ \mbox{and}\ B)=g(P(A),P(B|A))</math>
 
:is an [[associativity|associative]] binary operation.  All strictly increasing associative binary operations on the real numbers are isomorphic to multiplication of numbers in the interval [0, 1].  This function therefore may be taken to be multiplication.
 
*Suppose [''A'' & ''B''] is equivalent to [''C'' & ''D''].  If we acquire new information ''A'' and then acquire further new information ''B'', and update all probabilities each time, the updated probabilities will be the same as if we had first acquired new information ''C'' and then acquired further new information ''D''.  In view of the fact that multiplication of probabilities can be taken to be ordinary multiplication of real numbers, this becomes a [[functional equation]]
 
::<math>y\,f\left({f(z) \over y}\right)=z\,f\left({f(y) \over z}\right)</math>
 
:where ''f'' is as above.
 
Cox's theorem implies that any plausibility model that meets the
postulates is equivalent to the subjective probability model, i.e.,
can be converted to the probability model by rescaling.
 
==Implications of Cox's postulates==
The laws of probability derivable from these postulates are the following.<ref name="Jaynes2003">[[Edwin Thompson Jaynes]], ''Probability Theory: The Logic of Science,'' Cambridge University Press (2003). &mdash;  preprint version (1996) at http://omega.albany.edu:8008/JaynesBook.html; Chapters 1 to 3 of published version at http://bayes.wustl.edu/etj/prob/book.pdf
</ref> Here ''w''(''A''|''B'') is the "plausibility" of the proposition ''A'' given ''B'', and ''m'' is some positive number. Further, ''A''<sup>''C''</sup> represents the [[Complement (set theory)#Absolute complement|absolute complement]] of ''A''.
 
# Certainty is represented by ''w''(''A''|''B'') = 1.
# ''w''<sup>''m''</sup>(''A''|''B'') + ''w''<sup>''m''</sup>(''A''<sup>''C''</sup>|''B'') = 1
# ''w''(''A'', ''B''|''C'') = ''w''(''A''|''C'') ''w''(''B''|''A'', ''C'') = ''w''(''B''|''C'') ''w''(''A''|''B'', ''C'').
 
It is important to note that the postulates imply only these general properties. These are equivalent to the usual laws of probability assuming some conventions, namely that the scale of measurement is from zero to one, and the plausibility function, conventionally denoted ''P'' or Pr, is equal to ''w''<sup>''m''</sup>. (We could have equivalently chosen to measure probabilities from one to infinity, with infinity representing certain falsehood.) With these conventions, we obtain the laws of probability in a more familiar form:
 
# Certain truth is represented by Pr(''A''|''B'') = 1, and certain falsehood by Pr(''A''|''B'') = 0.
# Pr(''A''|''B'') + Pr(''A''<sup>''C''</sup>|''B'') = 1
# Pr(''A'', ''B''|''C'')  = Pr(''A''|''C'') Pr(''B''|''A'', ''C'') = Pr(''B''|''C'') Pr(''A''|''B'', ''C'').
 
Rule 2 is a rule for negation, and rule 3 is a rule for conjunction. Given that any proposition containing conjunction, disjunction, and negation can be equivalently rephrased using conjunction and negation alone (the [[conjunctive normal form]]), we can now handle any compound proposition.
 
The laws thus derived yield [[Measure (mathematics)|finite additivity]] of probability, but not [[Measure (mathematics)|countable additivity]]. The [[Probability theory|measure-theoretic formulation]] of Kolmogorov assumes that a probability measure is countably additive. This slightly stronger condition is necessary for the proof of certain theorems.
 
==Interpretation and further discussion==
Cox's theorem has come to be used as one of the [[theory of justification|justification]]s for the
use of [[Bayesian probability theory]]For example, in Jaynes<ref name="Jaynes2003" /> it is
discussed in detail in chapters 1 and 2 and is a cornerstone for the
rest of the book.  Probability is interpreted as a [[formal system]] of
[[logic]], the natural extension of [[Aristotelian logic]] (in which every
statement is either true or false) into the realm of reasoning in the
presence of uncertainty.
 
It has been debated to what degree the theorem excludes alternative models for reasoning about [[uncertainty]].  For example, if certain "unintuitive" mathematical assumptions were dropped then alternatives could be devised, e.g., an example provided by Halpern.<ref name="H99a" /> However Arnborg and Sjödin<ref name="AS1999" /><ref name="AS2000a" /><ref name="AS2000b" /> suggest additional
"common sense" postulates, which would allow the assumptions to be relaxed in some cases while still ruling out the Halpern example. Other approaches were devised by Hardy <ref>Michael Hardy, "Scaled Boolean algebras", ''[http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/01968858 Advances in Applied Mathematics]'', August 2002, pages 243&ndash;292 (or  [http://arxiv.org/abs/math.PR/0203249 preprint]); Hardy has said, "I assert there that I think Cox's assumptions are too strong, although I don't really say why. I do say what I would replace them with." (The quote is from a Wikipedia discussion page, not from the article.)</ref> or Dupré and Tipler.<ref name="rbp">Dupré, Maurice J., Tipler, Frank T. [http://ba.stat.cmu.edu/journal/2009/vol04/issue03/dupre.pdf ''New Axioms For Bayesian Probability''], Bayesian Analysis (2009), Number 3, pp. 599-606</ref>
 
The original formulation of Cox's theorem is in {{Harvtxt|Cox|1946}} which is extended with additional results and more discussion in {{Harvtxt|Cox|1961}}. Jaynes<ref name="Jaynes2003" /> cites Abel<ref>[[Niels Henrik Abel]] "Untersuchung der Functionen zweier unabhängig veränderlichen Gröszen ''x'' und ''y'', wie ''f''(''x'', ''y''), welche die Eigenschaft haben, dasz ''f''[''z'', ''f''(''x'',''y'')] eine symmetrische Function von ''z'', ''x'' und ''y'' ist.", ''Jour. Reine u. angew. Math.'' (Crelle's Jour.), 1, 11&ndash;15, (1826).</ref> for the first known use of the associativity functional equation. Aczél<ref>[[János Aczél (mathematician)|János Aczél]], ''Lectures on Functional Equations and their Applications,'' Academic Press, New York, (1966).</ref> provides a long proof of the "associativity equation" (pages 256-267). Jaynes <ref name="Jaynes2003" />(p27) reproduces the shorter proof by Cox in which differentiability is assumed. A guide to Cox's theorem by Van Horn aims at comprehensively introducing the reader to all these references.<ref>{{cite doi|10.1016/S0888-613X(03)00051-3}}</ref>
 
== See also ==
* [[Probability axioms]]
* [[Probability logic]]
 
==References==
{{Reflist}}
{{refbegin}}
* {{cite doi|10.1119/1.1990764}}
* {{cite book|first=R. T. |last=Cox |authorlink=Richard Threlkeld Cox |title=The Algebra of Probable Inference |publisher=Johns Hopkins University Press |location=Baltimore, MD |year=1961 |ref=harv}}
* [[Terrence L. Fine]], ''Theories of Probability; An examination of foundations,'' Academic Press, New York, (1973).
{{refend}}
 
[[Category:Probability theorems]]
[[Category:Probability interpretations]]
[[Category:Statistical theorems]]

Latest revision as of 04:12, 22 November 2014

My name is Mаkayla and I am studying Nursing and Desіgn and Technology at Dallas / United States.

Black and pink coach purses