|
|
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown) |
Line 1: |
Line 1: |
| {{about|the mathematical concept|number words denoting a position in a sequence ("first", "second", "third", etc.)|Ordinal number (linguistics)}}
| | I've been involved with the martial arts for over three decades now. I started researching the martial-arts when I was a kid that was 14-year old. I used to be the one that is shy. Of course, I received my share of intimidation, also.<br><br>But which was the furthest from my head after I joined the local Tae-Kwon-Do school in town. The truth is, my brother was a star soccer player in high school, and I needed to be exactly like him. So I believed if I could handle my toes better (i.e. discover karate), then maybe I would be a better baseball player.<br><br>My karate college was like most of others: non descript, underfunded, good-meant, and bunches of pleasure. I adored the fighting styles in the get-go, and quickly surrounded myself with everything associated with karate. I 'd martial arts courses on my program, martial-arts books on my shelves, and martial-arts cards on my bedroom walls.<br><br>I began to transform as an individual, as the years clicked by. Yes, I used to be still cumbersome, that pimply child and difficult. But a bit bigger went today. It was not unnoticeable. I felt better about myself. And another children quit teasing me as significantly.<br><br>My martial-arts instruction was continued by me through university. After graduating, I worked in Tokyo, Japan and had the unique opportunity to learn a number of martial arts during the 7 years I had been there, including judo, taekwondo, karate.<br>As soon as I returned to the United States, I joined a Hapkido college. Many people call it Korean Karate. Hapkido is not dissimilar to taekwondo. It's precisely the same kicks and punches as taekwondo. Hapkido now [https://Www.google.com/search?hl=en&gl=us&tbm=nws&q=offers+shared&btnI=lucky offers shared] tresses and motion that is circular much like aikido.<br><br>I am often asked what's the best martial-art for my child? Or what kind of karate school is best for my kid? My answer is this: All karate universities will vary. All fighting styles are not same. To say one school or fashion is preferable to another, is to state something like vanilla is better than chocolate.<br><br>The bottom line: The style that is finest is the one you're interest in. Then when you're buying a martial art for the child, don't get caught on the martial arts style. And don't join the very first karate college you see. Instead, take your time. If you adored this article and you simply would like to acquire more info regarding [http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=sbkH8y0NB8w Martial Arts Lessons in Grand rapids] kindly visit our own [http://www.Reddit.com/r/howto/search?q=web-page web-page]. Visit the martial-arts schools in your neighborhood. Talk with the teachers. See the students. Bound in a couple of martial-arts courses. See which school makes you joyful. That's the martial-arts school for you. |
| [[File:omega-exp-omega-labeled.svg|thumb|300px|Representation of the ordinal numbers up to ω<sup>ω</sup>. Each turn of the spiral represents one power of ω]]
| |
| In [[set theory]], an '''ordinal number''', or just '''ordinal''', is the [[order type]] of a [[well-order|well-ordered set]]. They are usually identified with [[hereditary property|hereditarily]] [[transitive set]]s. Ordinals are an extension of the [[natural number]]s different from [[integer]]s and from [[cardinal number|cardinal]]s. Like other kinds of numbers, ordinals can be added, multiplied, and exponentiated.
| |
| | |
| Ordinals were introduced by [[Georg Cantor]] in 1883 to accommodate [[infinite set|infinite]] sequences and to classify sets with certain kinds of [[order theory|order]] structures on them.<ref>Thorough introductions are given by Levy (1979) and Jech (2003).</ref> He derived them by accident while working on a problem concerning [[trigonometric series]].
| |
| | |
| Two sets ''S'' and ''S' '' have the same ''cardinality'' if there is a [[bijection]] between them (i.e. there exists a function f that is both [[injective]] and [[surjective]], that is it maps each element ''x'' of ''S'' to a unique element ''y'' = ''f''(''x'') of ''S' '' and each element ''y'' of ''S' '' comes from exactly one such element ''x'' of ''S'').
| |
| | |
| If a partial order < is defined on set ''S'', and a partial order <' is defined on set ''S' '', then the [[partially ordered set|poset]]s (''S'',<) and (''S' '',<') are [[order isomorphic]] if there is a [[bijection]] ''f'' that preserves the ordering. That is, ''f''(''a'') <' ''f''(''b'') if and only if ''a'' < ''b''. Every ''well ordered'' set (''S'',<) is order isomorphic to the set of ordinals less than one specific ordinal number (the order type of (''S'',<)) under their natural ordering.
| |
| | |
| The finite ordinals (and the finite cardinals) are the natural numbers: 0, 1, 2, …, since any two total orderings of a finite set are [[order isomorphic]]. The least infinite ordinal is ω, which is identified with the cardinal number [[Aleph null|<math>\aleph_0</math>]]. However in the transfinite case, beyond ω, ordinals draw a finer distinction than cardinals on account of their order information. Whereas there is only one countably infinite cardinal, namely <math>\aleph_0</math> itself, there are uncountably many countably infinite ordinals, namely
| |
| | |
| :ω, ω + 1, ω + 2, …, ω·2, ω·2 + 1, …, ω<sup>2</sup>, …, ω<sup>3</sup>, …, ω<sup>ω</sup>, …, ω<sup>ω<sup>ω</sup></sup>, …, ε<sub>0</sub>, ….
| |
| | |
| Here addition and multiplication are not commutative: in particular 1 + ω is ω rather than ω + 1 and likewise, 2·ω is ω rather than ω·2. The set of all countable ordinals constitutes the [[first uncountable ordinal|first uncountable ordinal ω<sub>1</sub>]], which is identified with the cardinal <math>\aleph_1</math> (next cardinal after <math>\aleph_0</math>). Well-ordered cardinals are identified with their [[initial ordinal]]s, i.e. the smallest ordinal of that [[cardinality]]. The ''cardinality of an ordinal'' defines a many to one association from ordinals to cardinals.
| |
| | |
| In general, each ordinal α is the ''order type of the set of ordinals'' strictly less than the ordinal α itself. This property permits every ordinal to be represented as the set of all ordinals less than it. Ordinals may be categorized as: zero, successor ordinals, and limit ordinals (of various [[Cofinality|cofinalities]]). Given a ''class of ordinals'', one can identify the α-th member of that class, i.e. one can index (count) them. Such a class is closed and unbounded if its indexing function is continuous and never stops. The '''[[Ordinal arithmetic#Cantor normal form|Cantor normal form]]''' uniquely represents each ordinal as a finite sum of ordinal powers of ω. However, this cannot form the basis of a universal ordinal notation due to such self-referential representations as ε<sub>0</sub> = ω<sup>ε<sub>0</sub></sup>. Larger and larger ordinals can be defined, but they become more and more difficult to describe. Any ordinal number can be made into a [[topological space]] by endowing it with the [[order topology]]; this topology is [[discrete topology|discrete]] if and only if the ordinal is a countable cardinal, i.e. at most ω. A subset of ω + 1 is open in the order topology if and only if either it is [[cofinite]] or it does not contain ω as an element.
| |
| | |
| == Ordinals extend the natural numbers ==
| |
| {{anchor|omega}}
| |
| <!-- Let us try to keep this section intuitive and understandable with almost no knowledge of mathematics. -->
| |
| A [[natural number]] (which, in this context, includes the number [[0 (number)|0]]) can be used for two purposes: to describe the ''size'' of a [[Set (mathematics)|set]], or to describe the ''position'' of an element in a sequence. When restricted to finite sets these two concepts coincide; there is only one way to put a finite set into a linear sequence, [[up to isomorphism]]. When dealing with infinite sets one has to distinguish between the notion of size, which leads to [[cardinal number]]s, and the notion of position, which is generalized by the ordinal numbers described here. This is because, while any set has only one size (its [[cardinality]]), there are many nonisomorphic well-orderings of any infinite set, as explained below.
| |
| | |
| Whereas the notion of cardinal number is associated with a set with no particular structure on it, the ordinals are intimately linked with the special kind of sets that are called [[well-order]]ed (so intimately linked, in fact, that some mathematicians make no distinction between the two concepts). A well-ordered set is a [[totally ordered]] set (given any two elements one defines a smaller and a larger one in a coherent way) in which there is no infinite ''decreasing'' sequence (however, there may be infinite increasing sequences); equivalently, every non-empty subset of the set has a least element. Ordinals may be used to label the elements of any given well-ordered set (the smallest element being labelled 0, the one after that 1, the next one 2, "and so on") and to measure the "length" of the whole set by the least ordinal that is not a label for an element of the set. This "length" is called the ''order type'' of the set.
| |
| | |
| Any ordinal is defined by the set of ordinals that precede it: in fact, the most common definition of ordinals ''identifies'' each ordinal ''as'' the set of ordinals that precede it. For example, the ordinal 42 is the order type of the ordinals less than it, i.e., the ordinals from 0 (the smallest of all ordinals) to 41 (the immediate predecessor of 42), and it is generally identified as the set {0,1,2,…,41}. Conversely, any set (''S'') of ordinals that is downward-closed—meaning that for any ordinal α in S and any ordinal β < α, β is also in the set—is (or can be identified with) an ordinal.
| |
| | |
| So far we have mentioned only finite ordinals, which are the natural numbers. But there are infinite ones as well: the smallest infinite ordinal is '''ω''', which is the order type of the natural numbers (finite ordinals) and that can even be identified with the ''set'' of natural numbers (indeed, the set of natural numbers is well-ordered—as is any set of ordinals—and since it is downward closed it can be identified with the ordinal associated with it, which is exactly how we define ω).
| |
| | |
| [[File:Omega squared.png|thumb|right|256px|A graphical “matchstick” representation of the ordinal ω². Each stick corresponds to an ordinal of the form ω·''m''+''n'' where ''m'' and ''n'' are natural numbers.]]
| |
| | |
| Perhaps a clearer intuition of ordinals can be formed by examining a first few of them: as mentioned above, they start with the natural numbers, 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, … After ''all'' natural numbers comes the first infinite ordinal, ω, and after that come ω+1, ω+2, ω+3, and so on. (Exactly what addition means will be defined later on: just consider them as names.) After all of these come ω·2 (which is ω+ω), ω·2+1, ω·2+2, and so on, then ω·3, and then later on ω·4. Now the set of ordinals we form in this way (the ω·''m''+''n'', where ''m'' and ''n'' are natural numbers) must itself have an ordinal associated with it: and that is ω<sup>2</sup>. Further on, there will be ω<sup>3</sup>, then ω<sup>4</sup>, and so on, and ω<sup>ω</sup>, then ω<sup>ω²</sup>, and much later on ε<sub>0</sub> ([[Epsilon_numbers_(mathematics)|epsilon nought]]) (to give a few examples of relatively small—countable—ordinals). We can go on in this way indefinitely far ("indefinitely far" is exactly what ordinals are good at: basically every time one says "and so on" when enumerating ordinals, it defines a larger ordinal). The smallest uncountable ordinal is the set of all countable ordinals, expressed as ω<sub>1</sub>.
| |
| | |
| == Definitions ==
| |
| | |
| === Well-ordered sets ===
| |
| {{See|Ordered set}}
| |
| | |
| In a [[well-order]]ed set, every non-empty subset has a smallest element. Given the [[axiom of dependent choice]], this is equivalent to just saying that the set is [[totally ordered]] and there is no infinite decreasing sequence, something perhaps easier to visualize. In practice, the importance of well-ordering is justified by the possibility of applying [[transfinite induction]], which says, essentially, that any property that passes on from the predecessors of an element to that element itself must be true of all elements (of the given well-ordered set). If the states of a computation (computer program or game) can be well-ordered in such a way that each step is followed by a "lower" step, then you can be sure that the computation will terminate.
| |
| | |
| Now we don't want to distinguish between two well-ordered sets if they only differ in the "labeling of their elements", or more formally: if we can pair off the elements of the first set with the elements of the second set such that if one element is smaller than another in the first set, then the partner of the first element is smaller than the partner of the second element in the second set, and vice versa. Such a one-to-one correspondence is called an [[order isomorphism]] and the two well-ordered sets are said to be order-isomorphic, or ''similar'' (obviously this is an [[equivalence relation]]). Provided there exists an order isomorphism between two well-ordered sets, the order isomorphism is unique: this makes it quite justifiable to consider the two sets as essentially identical, and to seek a "canonical" representative of the isomorphism type (class). This is exactly what the ordinals provide, and it also provides a canonical labeling of the elements of any well-ordered set.
| |
| | |
| So we essentially wish to define an ordinal as an isomorphism class of well-ordered sets: that is, as an [[equivalence class]] for the [[equivalence relation]] of "being order-isomorphic". There is a technical difficulty involved, however, in the fact that the equivalence class is too large to be a set in the usual [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory|Zermelo–Fraenkel]] (ZF) formalization of set theory. But this is not a serious difficulty. We will say that the ordinal is the ''[[order type]]'' of any set in the class.
| |
| | |
| === Definition of an ordinal as an equivalence class ===
| |
| | |
| The original definition of ordinal number, found for example in [[Principia Mathematica]], defines the order type of a well-ordering as the set of all well-orderings similar (order-isomorphic) to that well-ordering: in other words, an ordinal number is genuinely an equivalence class of well-ordered sets. This definition must be abandoned in [[Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory|ZF]] and related systems of [[axiomatic set theory]] because these equivalence classes are too large to form a set. However, this definition still can be used in [[type theory]] and in Quine's axiomatic set theory [[New Foundations]] and related systems (where it affords a rather surprising alternative solution to the [[Burali-Forti paradox]] of the largest ordinal).
| |
| | |
| === Von Neumann definition of ordinals ===
| |
| | |
| Rather than defining an ordinal as an ''equivalence class'' of well-ordered sets, we will define it as a particular well-ordered set that (canonically) represents the class. Thus, an ordinal number will be a well-ordered set; and every well-ordered set will be order-isomorphic to exactly one ordinal number.
| |
| | |
| The standard definition, suggested by [[John von Neumann]], is: ''each ordinal is the well-ordered set of all smaller ordinals''. In symbols, λ = [0,λ).<ref name="von Neumann1923pp199-208">{{Harvnb|von Neumann|1923}}</ref><ref>Levy (1979, p. 52) attributes the idea to unpublished work of Zermelo in 1916 and several papers by von Neumann the 1920s.</ref> Formally:
| |
| | |
| :A set ''S'' is an ordinal if and only if ''S'' is [[strict order|strictly]] well-ordered with respect to set membership and every element of ''S'' is also a subset of ''S''.
| |
| | |
| Note that the natural numbers are ordinals by this definition. For instance, 2 is an element of 4 = {0, 1, 2, 3}, and 2 is equal to {0, 1} and so it is a subset of {0, 1, 2, 3}.
| |
| | |
| It can be shown by [[transfinite induction]] that every well-ordered set is order-isomorphic to exactly one of these ordinals, that is, there is an order preserving [[bijective function]] between them.
| |
| | |
| Furthermore, the elements of every ordinal are ordinals themselves. Whenever you have two ordinals ''S'' and ''T'', ''S'' is an element of ''T'' if and only if ''S'' is a [[proper subset]] of ''T''. Moreover, either ''S'' is an element of ''T'', or ''T'' is an element of ''S'', or they are equal. So every set of ordinals is [[total order|totally ordered]]. Further, every set of ordinals is well-ordered. This generalizes the fact that every set of natural numbers is well-ordered.
| |
| | |
| Consequently, every ordinal ''S'' is a set having as elements precisely the ordinals smaller than ''S''. For example, every set of ordinals has a [[supremum]], the ordinal obtained by taking the union of all the ordinals in the set. This union exists regardless of the set's size, by the [[axiom of union]].
| |
| | |
| The class of all ordinals is not a set. If it were a set, one could show that it was an ordinal and thus a member of itself, which would contradict its ''strict'' ordering by membership. This is the [[Burali-Forti paradox]]. The class of all ordinals is variously called "Ord", "ON", or "∞".
| |
| | |
| An ordinal is [[finite set|finite]] if and only if the opposite order is also well-ordered, which is the case if and only if each of its subsets has a [[maximum]].
| |
| | |
| === Other definitions ===
| |
| | |
| There are other modern formulations of the definition of ordinal. For example, assuming the [[axiom of regularity]], the following are equivalent for a set ''x'':
| |
| *''x'' is an ordinal,
| |
| *''x'' is a [[transitive set]], and set membership is [[trichotomy (mathematics)|trichotomous]] on ''x'',
| |
| *''x'' is a transitive set [[total order|totally ordered]] by set inclusion,
| |
| *''x'' is a transitive set of transitive sets.
| |
| These definitions cannot be used in [[non-well-founded set theory|non-well-founded set theories]]. In set theories with [[urelement]]s, one has to further make sure that the definition excludes urelements from appearing in ordinals.
| |
| | |
| ==Transfinite sequence==
| |
| If α is a [[limit ordinal]] and ''X'' is a set, an α-indexed sequence of elements of ''X'' is a function from α to ''X''. This concept, a '''transfinite sequence''' or '''ordinal-indexed sequence''', is a generalization of the concept of a [[sequence]]. An ordinary sequence corresponds to the case α = ω.
| |
| | |
| == Transfinite induction ==
| |
| {{main|Transfinite induction}}
| |
| | |
| === What is transfinite induction? ===
| |
| | |
| Transfinite induction holds in any [[well-order]]ed set, but it is so important in relation to ordinals that it is worth restating here.
| |
| | |
| :Any property that passes from the set of ordinals smaller than a given ordinal ''α'' to ''α'' itself, is true of all ordinals.
| |
| | |
| That is, if ''P''(''α'') is true whenever ''P''(''β'') is true for all ''β''<''α'', then ''P''(''α'') is true for ''all'' ''α''. Or, more practically: in order to prove a property ''P'' for all ordinals ''α'', one can assume that it is already known for all smaller ''β''<''α''.
| |
| | |
| === Transfinite recursion ===
| |
| | |
| Transfinite induction can be used not only to prove things, but also to define them. Such a definition is normally said to be by [[transfinite recursion]] – the proof that the result is well-defined uses transfinite induction. Let ''F'' denote a (class) function ''F'' to be defined on the ordinals. The idea now is that, in defining ''F''(α) for an unspecified ordinal α, one may assume that ''F''(β) is already defined for all {{nowrap|β < α}} and thus give a formula for ''F''(α) in terms of these ''F''(β). It then follows by transfinite induction that there is one and only one function satisfying the recursion formula up to and including α.
| |
| | |
| Here is an example of definition by transfinite recursion on the ordinals (more will be given later): define function ''F'' by letting ''F''(α) be the smallest ordinal not in the class <span style="white-space:nowrap;">{''F''(β) | β < α}</span>, that is, the class consisting of all ''F''(β) for {{nowrap|β < α}}. This definition assumes the ''F''(β) known in the very process of defining ''F''; this apparent vicious circle is exactly what definition by transfinite recursion permits. In fact, ''F''(0) makes sense since there is no ordinal {{nowrap|β < 0}}, and the class <span style="white-space:nowrap;">{''F''(β) | β < 0}</span> is empty. So ''F''(0) is equal to 0 (the smallest ordinal of all). Now that ''F''(0) is known, the definition applied to ''F''(1) makes sense (it is the smallest ordinal not in the singleton class {{nowrap|1={''F''(0)} = {0}}}), and so on (the ''and so on'' is exactly transfinite induction). It turns out that this example is not very exciting, since provably {{nowrap|1=''F''(α) = α}} for all ordinals α, which can be shown, precisely, by transfinite induction.
| |
| | |
| === Successor and limit ordinals ===
| |
| Any nonzero ordinal has the minimum element, zero. It may or may not have a maximum element. For example, 42 has maximum 41 and ω+6 has maximum ω+5. On the other hand, ω does not have a maximum since there is no largest natural number. If an ordinal has a maximum α, then it is the next ordinal after α, and it is called a ''[[successor ordinal]]'', namely the successor of α, written α+1. In the von Neumann definition of ordinals, the successor of α is <math>\alpha\cup\{\alpha\}</math> since its elements are those of α and α itself.<ref name="von Neumann1923pp199-208" />
| |
| | |
| A nonzero ordinal that is ''not'' a successor is called a ''[[limit ordinal]]''. One justification for this term is that a limit ordinal is indeed the [[limit point|limit]] in a topological sense of all smaller ordinals (under the [[order topology]]).
| |
| | |
| When <math>\langle \alpha_{\iota} | \iota < \gamma \rangle</math> is an ordinal-indexed sequence, indexed by a limit γ and the sequence is ''increasing'', i.e. <math>\alpha_{\iota} < \alpha_{\rho}\!</math> whenever <math>\iota < \rho,\!</math> we define its ''limit'' to be the least upper bound of the set <math>\{ \alpha_{\iota} | \iota < \gamma \},\!</math> that is, the smallest ordinal (it always exists) greater than any term of the sequence. In this sense, a limit ordinal is the limit of all smaller ordinals (indexed by itself). Put more directly, it is the supremum of the set of smaller ordinals.
| |
| | |
| Another way of defining a limit ordinal is to say that α is a limit ordinal if and only if:
| |
| | |
| :There is an ordinal less than α and whenever ζ is an ordinal less than α, then there exists an ordinal ξ such that ζ < ξ < α.
| |
| | |
| So in the following sequence:
| |
| | |
| :0, 1, 2, ... , ω, ω+1
| |
| | |
| ω is a limit ordinal because for any smaller ordinal (in this example, a natural number) we can find another ordinal (natural number) larger than it, but still less than ω.
| |
| | |
| Thus, every ordinal is either zero, or a successor (of a well-defined predecessor), or a limit. This distinction is important, because many definitions by transfinite induction rely upon it. Very often, when defining a function ''F'' by transfinite induction on all ordinals, one defines ''F''(0), and ''F''(α+1) assuming ''F''(α) is defined, and then, for limit ordinals δ one defines ''F''(δ) as the limit of the ''F''(β) for all β<δ (either in the sense of ordinal limits, as we have just explained, or for some other notion of limit if ''F'' does not take ordinal values). Thus, the interesting step in the definition is the successor step, not the limit ordinals. Such functions (especially for ''F'' nondecreasing and taking ordinal values) are called continuous. We will see that ordinal addition, multiplication and exponentiation are continuous as functions of their second argument.
| |
| | |
| === Indexing classes of ordinals ===
| |
| | |
| We have mentioned that any well-ordered set is similar (order-isomorphic) to a unique ordinal number <math>\alpha</math>, or, in other words, that its elements can be indexed in increasing fashion by the ordinals less than <math>\alpha</math>. This applies, in particular, to any set of ordinals: any set of ordinals is naturally indexed by the ordinals less than some <math>\alpha</math>. The same holds, with a slight modification, for ''classes'' of ordinals (a collection of ordinals, possibly too large to form a set, defined by some property): any class of ordinals can be indexed by ordinals (and, when the class is unbounded in the class of all ordinals, this puts it in class-bijection with the class of all ordinals). So we can freely speak of the <math>\gamma</math>-th element in the class (with the convention that the “0-th” is the smallest, the “1-th” is the next smallest, and so on). Formally, the definition is by transfinite induction: the <math>\gamma</math>-th element of the class is defined (provided it has already been defined for all <math>\beta<\gamma</math>), as the smallest element greater than the <math>\beta</math>-th element for all <math>\beta<\gamma</math>.
| |
| | |
| We can apply this, for example, to the class of limit ordinals: the <math>\gamma</math>-th ordinal, which is either a limit or zero is <math>\omega\cdot\gamma</math> (see [[ordinal arithmetic]] for the definition of multiplication of ordinals). Similarly, we can consider ''[[additively indecomposable ordinal]]s'' (meaning a nonzero ordinal that is not the sum of two strictly smaller ordinals): the <math>\gamma</math>-th additively indecomposable ordinal is indexed as <math>\omega^\gamma</math>. The technique of indexing classes of ordinals is often useful in the context of fixed points: for example, the <math>\gamma</math>-th ordinal <math>\alpha</math> such that <math>\omega^\alpha=\alpha</math> is written <math>\varepsilon_\gamma</math>. These are called the "[[Epsilon numbers (mathematics)|epsilon numbers]]".
| |
| | |
| === Closed unbounded sets and classes ===
| |
| | |
| A class <math>C</math> of ordinals is said to be '''unbounded''', or '''cofinal''', when given any ordinal <math>\alpha</math>, there is a <math>\beta</math> in <math>C</math> such that <math>\alpha < \beta</math> (then the class must be a proper class, i.e., it cannot be a set). It is said to be '''closed''' when the limit of a sequence of ordinals in the class is again in the class: or, equivalently, when the indexing (class-)function <math>F</math> is continuous in the sense that, for <math>\delta</math> a limit ordinal, <math>F(\delta)</math> (the <math>\delta</math>-th ordinal in the class) is the limit of all <math>F(\gamma)</math> for <math>\gamma<\delta</math>; this is also the same as being closed, in the [[topological space|topological]] sense, for the [[order topology]] (to avoid talking of topology on proper classes, one can demand that the intersection of the class with any given ordinal is closed for the order topology on that ordinal, this is again equivalent).
| |
| | |
| Of particular importance are those classes of ordinals that are [[club set|closed and unbounded]], sometimes called '''clubs'''. For example, the class of all limit ordinals is closed and unbounded: this translates the fact that there is always a limit ordinal greater than a given ordinal, and that a limit of limit ordinals is a limit ordinal (a fortunate fact if the terminology is to make any sense at all!). The class of additively indecomposable ordinals, or the class of <math>\varepsilon_\cdot</math> ordinals, or the class of [[#Ordinals and cardinals|cardinals]], are all closed unbounded; the set of [[#Cofinality|regular]] cardinals, however, is unbounded but not closed, and any finite set of ordinals is closed but not unbounded.
| |
| | |
| A class is stationary if it has a nonempty intersection with every closed unbounded class. All superclasses of closed unbounded classes are stationary, and stationary classes are unbounded, but there are stationary classes that are not closed and stationary classes that have no closed unbounded subclass (such as the class of all limit ordinals with countable cofinality). Since the intersection of two closed unbounded classes is closed and unbounded, the intersection of a stationary class and a closed unbounded class is stationary. But the intersection of two stationary classes may be empty, e.g. the class of ordinals with cofinality ω with the class of ordinals with uncountable cofinality.
| |
| | |
| Rather than formulating these definitions for (proper) classes of ordinals, we can formulate them for sets of ordinals below a given ordinal <math>\alpha</math>: A subset of a limit ordinal <math>\alpha</math> is said to be unbounded (or cofinal) under <math>\alpha</math> provided any ordinal less than <math>\alpha</math> is less than some ordinal in the set. More generally, we can call a subset of any ordinal <math>\alpha</math> cofinal in <math>\alpha</math> provided every ordinal less than <math>\alpha</math> is less than ''or equal to'' some ordinal in the set. The subset is said to be closed under <math>\alpha</math> provided it is closed for the order topology ''in'' <math>\alpha</math>, i.e. a limit of ordinals in the set is either in the set or equal to <math>\alpha</math> itself.
| |
| | |
| == Arithmetic of ordinals ==
| |
| {{main|Ordinal arithmetic}}
| |
| | |
| There are three usual operations on ordinals: addition, multiplication, and (ordinal) exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an explicit well-ordered set that represents the operation or by using transfinite recursion. Cantor normal form provides a standardized way of writing ordinals. The so-called "natural" arithmetical operations retain commutativity at the expense of continuity.
| |
| | |
| == Ordinals and cardinals ==
| |
| | |
| === Initial ordinal of a cardinal ===
| |
| | |
| Each ordinal has an associated [[Cardinal number|cardinal]], its cardinality, obtained by simply forgetting the order. Any well-ordered set having that ordinal as its order-type has the same cardinality. The smallest ordinal having a given cardinal as its cardinality is called the initial ordinal of that cardinal. Every finite ordinal (natural number) is initial, but most infinite ordinals are not initial. The [[axiom of choice]] is equivalent to the statement that every set can be well-ordered, i.e. that every cardinal has an initial ordinal. In this case, it is traditional to identify the cardinal number with its initial ordinal, and we say that the initial ordinal ''is'' a cardinal.
| |
| | |
| Cantor used the cardinality to partition ordinals into classes. He referred to the natural numbers as the '''first number class''', the ordinals with cardinality <math>\aleph_0</math> (the countably infinite ordinals) as the '''second number class''' and generally, the ordinals with cardinality <math>\aleph_{n-2}</math> as the ''' ''n''-th number class'''.<ref>Dauben (1990:97)</ref>
| |
| | |
| The α-th infinite initial ordinal is written <math>\omega_\alpha</math>. Its cardinality is written <math>\aleph_\alpha</math>. For example, the cardinality of ω<sub>0</sub> = ω is <math>\aleph_0</math>, which is also the cardinality of ω<sup>2</sup> or ε<sub>0</sub> (all are countable ordinals). So (assuming the axiom of choice) we identify ω with <math>\aleph_0</math>, except that the notation <math>\aleph_0</math> is used when writing cardinals, and ω when writing ordinals (this is important since, for example, <math>\aleph_0^2</math> = <math>\aleph_0</math> whereas <math>\omega^2>\omega</math>). Also, <math>\omega_1</math> is the smallest uncountable ordinal (to see that it exists, consider the set of equivalence classes of well-orderings of the natural numbers: each such well-ordering defines a countable ordinal, and <math>\omega_1</math> is the order type of that set), <math>\omega_2</math> is the smallest ordinal whose cardinality is greater than <math>\aleph_1</math>, and so on, and <math>\omega_\omega</math> is the limit of the <math>\omega_n</math> for natural numbers ''n'' (any limit of cardinals is a cardinal, so this limit is indeed the first cardinal after all the <math>\omega_n</math>).
| |
| | |
| See also [[Von Neumann cardinal assignment]].
| |
| | |
| === Cofinality ===
| |
| | |
| The [[cofinality]] of an ordinal <math>\alpha</math> is the smallest ordinal <math>\delta</math> that is the order type of a [[cofinal (mathematics)|cofinal]] subset of <math>\alpha</math>. Notice that a number of authors define cofinality or use it only for limit ordinals. The cofinality of a set of ordinals or any other well ordered set is the cofinality of the order type of that set.
| |
| | |
| Thus for a limit ordinal, there exists a <math>\delta</math>-indexed strictly increasing sequence with limit <math>\alpha</math>. For example, the cofinality of ω² is ω, because the sequence ω·''m'' (where ''m'' ranges over the natural numbers) tends to ω²; but, more generally, any countable limit ordinal has cofinality ω. An uncountable limit ordinal may have either cofinality ω as does <math>\omega_\omega</math> or an uncountable cofinality.
| |
| | |
| The cofinality of 0 is 0. And the cofinality of any successor ordinal is 1. The cofinality of any limit ordinal is at least <math>\omega</math>.
| |
| | |
| An ordinal that is equal to its cofinality is called regular and it is always an initial ordinal. Any limit of regular ordinals is a limit of initial ordinals and thus is also initial even if it is not regular, which it usually is not. If the Axiom of Choice, then <math>\omega_{\alpha+1}</math> is regular for each α. In this case, the ordinals 0, 1, <math>\omega</math>, <math>\omega_1</math>, and <math>\omega_2</math> are regular, whereas 2, 3, <math>\omega_\omega</math>, and ω<sub>ω·2</sub> are initial ordinals that are not regular.
| |
| | |
| The cofinality of any ordinal ''α'' is a regular ordinal, i.e. the cofinality of the cofinality of ''α'' is the same as the cofinality of ''α''. So the cofinality operation is [[idempotent]].
| |
| | |
| == Some “large” countable ordinals ==
| |
| {{details|Large countable ordinal}}
| |
| | |
| We have already mentioned (see [[Ordinal arithmetic#Cantor normal form|Cantor normal form]]) the ordinal ε<sub>0</sub>, which is the smallest satisfying the equation <math>\omega^\alpha = \alpha</math>, so it is the limit of the sequence 0, 1, <math>\omega</math>, <math>\omega^\omega</math>, <math>\omega^{\omega^\omega}</math>, etc. Many ordinals can be defined in such a manner as fixed points of certain ordinal functions (the <math>\iota</math>-th ordinal such that <math>\omega^\alpha = \alpha</math> is called <math>\varepsilon_\iota</math>, then we could go on trying to find the <math>\iota</math>-th ordinal such that <math>\varepsilon_\alpha = \alpha</math>, “and so on”, but all the subtlety lies in the “and so on”). We can try to do this systematically, but no matter what system is used to define and construct ordinals, there is always an ordinal that lies just above all the ordinals constructed by the system. Perhaps the most important ordinal that limits a system of construction in this manner is the [[Church–Kleene ordinal]], <math>\omega_1^{\mathrm{CK}}</math> (despite the <math>\omega_1</math> in the name, this ordinal is countable), which is the smallest ordinal that cannot in any way be represented by a [[computable function]] (this can be made rigorous, of course). Considerably large ordinals can be defined below <math>\omega_1^{\mathrm{CK}}</math>, however, which measure the “proof-theoretic strength” of certain [[formal system]]s (for example, <math>\varepsilon_0</math> measures the strength of [[Peano axioms|Peano arithmetic]]). Large ordinals can also be defined above the Church-Kleene ordinal, which are of interest in various parts of logic.
| |
| | |
| == Topology and ordinals ==
| |
| {{details|Order topology}}
| |
| Any ordinal can be made into a [[topological space]] in a natural way by endowing it with the [[order topology]].
| |
| See the [[Order topology#Topology and ordinals|Topology and ordinals]] section of the "Order topology" article.
| |
| | |
| ==Downward closed sets of ordinals==
| |
| A set is [[downward closed]] if anything less than an element of the set is also in the set. If a set of ordinals is downward closed, then that set is an ordinal—the least ordinal not in the set. <!-- Suppose a property is such that if is true for an ordinal it is true for all smaller ones. This means that it holds for a [[downward closed]] set of ordinals, which is itself an ordinal. Thus the smallest ordinal that does not have the property is the set of ordinals that has the property. -->
| |
| | |
| Examples:
| |
| *The set of ordinals less than 3 is 3 = { 0, 1, 2 }, the smallest ordinal not less than 3.
| |
| *The set of finite ordinals is infinite, the smallest infinite ordinal: ω.
| |
| *The set of countable ordinals is uncountable, the smallest uncountable ordinal: ω<sub>1</sub>.
| |
| | |
| ==See also==
| |
| *[[Counting]]
| |
| *[[Regnal number|Regnal ordinal]]
| |
| *[[Order topology#Ordinal space|Ordinal space]]
| |
| | |
| ==Notes==
| |
| {{reflist}}
| |
| | |
| ==References==
| |
| * [[Georg Cantor|Cantor, G.]], (1897), ''Beitrage zur Begrundung der transfiniten Mengenlehre. II'' (tr.: Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers II), Mathematische Annalen 49, 207-246 [http://www.archive.org/details/117770262 English translation].
| |
| * [[John Horton Conway|Conway, J. H.]] and [[Richard K. Guy|Guy, R. K.]] "Cantor's Ordinal Numbers." In ''The Book of Numbers''. New York: Springer-Verlag, pp. 266–267 and 274, 1996.
| |
| * Dauben, Joseph Warren, (1990), [http://books.google.com/books?id=-cpFeTPJXDIC&lpg=PA100&ots=-OcWWxn5se&dq=%22second%20number%20class%22&pg=PA95#v=onepage&q=&f=false Georg Cantor: his mathematics and philosophy of the infinite]. Chapter 5: The Mathematics of Cantor's ''Grundlagen''. ISBN 0-691-02447-2
| |
| * {{Citation | last = Hamilton | first = A. G. | title = Numbers, Sets, and Axioms : the Apparatus of Mathematics | year = 1982 | location = New York | publisher = Cambridge University Press | isbn = 0-521-24509-5}} See Ch. 6, "Ordinal and cardinal numbers"
| |
| *[[Akihiro Kanamori|Kanamori, A.]], [http://math.bu.edu/people/aki/16.pdf ''Set Theory from Cantor to Cohen''], to appear in: Andrew Irvine and John H. Woods (editors), ''The Handbook of the Philosophy of Science'', volume 4, Mathematics, Cambridge University Press.
| |
| *{{Citation | last1=Levy | first1=A. | title=Basic Set Theory | publisher=[[Springer-Verlag]] | location=Berlin, New York | year=1979}} Reprinted 2002, Dover. ISBN 0-486-42079-5
| |
| *{{Citation | last1=Jech | first1=Thomas | title=[[Set Theory]] | publisher= [[Springer-Verlag]]| location=Berlin, New York | series=Springer Monographs in Mathematics | year=2003}}
| |
| * Sierpiński, W. (1965). ''Cardinal and Ordinal Numbers'' (2nd ed.). Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Also defines ordinal operations in terms of the Cantor Normal Form.
| |
| * [[Patrick Suppes|Suppes, P.]] (1960), ''Axiomatic Set Theory'', D.Van Nostrand Company Inc., ISBN 0-486-61630-4
| |
| * {{Citation|last=von Neumann|first=Johann|author-link=John von Neumann|year=1923|title=Zur Einführung der trasfiniten Zahlen|journal=Acta litterarum ac scientiarum Ragiae Universitatis Hungaricae Francisco-Josephinae, Sectio scientiarum mathematicarum|publisher=|pages=199–208|volume=1|url=http://acta.fyx.hu/acta/showCustomerArticle.action?id=4981&dataObjectType=article&returnAction=showCustomerVolume&sessionDataSetId=39716d660ae98d02&style=}}
| |
| * {{Citation|last=von Neumann|first=John|author-link=John von Neumann|editor=Jean van Heijenoort|origyear=1923|date=January 2002|title=From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931|chapter=On the introduction of transfinite numbers|edition=3rd|publisher=Harvard University Press|pages=346–354|isbn=0-674-32449-8|url=http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674324497}} - English translation of {{Harvnb|von Neumann|1923}}.
| |
| | |
| ==External links==
| |
| {{Wiktionary|ordinal}}
| |
| * {{springer|title=Ordinal number|id=p/o070180}}
| |
| * {{MathWorld | urlname=OrdinalNumber| title=Ordinal Number}}
| |
| *[http://www.apronus.com/provenmath/ordinals.htm Ordinals at ProvenMath]
| |
| *[http://www.springerlink.com/content/n3797702v6422612/ Beitraege zur Begruendung der transfiniten Mengenlehre] Cantor's original paper published in Mathematische Annalen 49(2), 1897
| |
| *[http://mtnmath.com/ord/index.html Ordinal calculator] [[GNU General Public License|GPL'd]] free software for computing with ordinals and ordinal notations
| |
| | |
| {{countable ordinals}}
| |
| {{Number Systems}}
| |
| {{Set theory}}
| |
| | |
| [[Category:Ordinal numbers| ]]
| |
| [[Category:Wellfoundedness]]
| |