Betti number: Difference between revisions

From formulasearchengine
Jump to navigation Jump to search
en>Enyokoyama
en>Zulon
 
(One intermediate revision by one other user not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
In [[mathematics]], the '''dimension theorem for vector spaces''' states that all [[Basis (linear algebra)|bases]] of a [[vector space]] have equally many elements. This number of elements may be finite, or given by an infinite [[cardinal number]], and defines the [[Dimension (vector space)|dimension]] of the space.
Gabrielle is what her hubby loves to call a though she doesn't genuinely like being called of that ranking. As a woman what she really likes is mah jongg but she hasn't ever made a dime by using it. Software developing is where her [http://www.Encyclopedia.com/searchresults.aspx?q=primary primary] income comes from but nevertheless , soon her husband and consequently her will start their personal own [http://Www.sharkbayte.com/keyword/business business]. For a while she's not long ago in Massachusetts. Go to her website to pick out more: http://circuspartypanama.com/<br><br>Feel free to visit my web site [http://circuspartypanama.com/ clash of clans hack no survey no jailbreak]
 
Formally, the '''dimension theorem for vector spaces''' states that
 
:Given a [[vector space]] ''V'', any two [[linearly independent]] [[generating set]]s (in other words, any two bases) have the same [[cardinality]].
 
If ''V'' is [[finitely generated module|finitely generated]], then it has a finite basis, and the result says that any two bases have the same number of elements.
 
While the proof of the existence of a basis for any vector space in the general case requires [[Zorn's lemma]] and is in fact equivalent to the [[axiom of choice]], the uniqueness of the cardinality of the basis requires only the [[ultrafilter lemma]],<ref>Howard, P., Rubin, J.: "Consequences of the axiom of choice" - Mathematical Surveys and Monographs, vol 59 (1998) ISSN 0076-5376.</ref> which is strictly weaker (the proof given below, however, assumes [[trichotomy (mathematics)|trichotomy]], i.e., that all [[cardinal number]]s are comparable, a statement which is also equivalent to the axiom of choice). The theorem can be generalized to arbitrary [[module (mathematics)|''R''-modules]] for rings ''R'' having [[invariant basis number]].
 
The theorem for finitely generated case can be proved with elementary arguments of [[linear algebra]], and requires no forms of the axiom of choice.
 
==Proof==
 
Assume that { ''a''<sub>''i''</sub>: ''i'' ∈ ''I'' } and
{ ''b''<sub>''j''</sub>: ''j'' ∈ ''J'' } are both bases, with the cardinality of ''I'' bigger than the cardinality of ''J''. From this assumption we will derive a contradiction.
 
===Case 1===
Assume that ''I'' is infinite.
 
Every ''b''<sub>''j''</sub> can be written as a finite sum
:<math>b_j = \sum_{i\in E_j} \lambda_{i,j} a_i </math>, where <math>E_j</math> is a finite subset of <math>I</math>.
Since the cardinality of ''I'' is greater than that of ''J'' and the ''E<sub>j</sub>'s'' are finite subsets of ''I'', the cardinality of ''I'' is also bigger than the cardinality of <math>\bigcup_{j\in J} E_j</math>.  (Note that this argument works ''only'' for infinite ''I''.)  So there is some <math>i_0\in I</math> which does not appear
in any <math>E_j</math>.  The corresponding <math>a_{i_0}</math> can be expressed as a finite linear combination of <math>b_j</math>'s, which in turn can be expressed as finite linear combination of <math> a_i</math>'s, not involving <math>a_{i_0}</math>.  Hence <math> a_{i_0}</math> is linearly dependent on the other <math>a_i</math>'s.
 
===Case 2===
Now assume that ''I'' is finite and of cardinality bigger than the cardinality of ''J''.  Write ''m'' and ''n'' for the cardinalities of ''I'' and ''J'', respectively.
Every ''a''<sub>''i''</sub> can be written as a sum
:<math>a_i = \sum_{j\in J} \mu_{i,j} b_j </math>
The matrix  <math> (\mu_{i,j}: i\in I, j\in J)</math>  has ''n'' columns (the ''j''-th column is the
''m''-tuple <math> (\mu_{i,j}: i\in I)</math>), so it has rank at most ''n''. [[Vicious circle|This means]] that [[Rank (linear algebra)#Proofs that column rank = row rank|its ''m'' rows cannot be linearly independent]].   Write <math>r_i = (\mu_{i,j}: j\in J)</math> for the ''i''-th row, then there is a nontrivial
linear combination
:<math> \sum_{i\in I}  \nu_i r_i = 0</math>
But then also <math>\sum_{i\in I} \nu_i a_i = \sum_{i\in I} \nu_i \sum_{j\in J} \mu_{i,j} b_j = \sum_{j\in J} \biggl(\sum_{i\in I} \nu_i\mu_{i,j} \biggr) b_j = 0, </math>
so the <math> a_i</math> are linearly dependent.
 
====Alternative Proof====
The proof above uses several non-trivial results.  If these results are not carefully established in advance, the proof may give rise to circular reasoning. Here is a proof of the finite case which requires less prior development.
 
'''Theorem 1:''' If <math>A = (a_1,\dots,a_n) \subseteq V</math> is a linearly independent [[tuple]] in a vector space <math>V</math>, and <math>B_0 = (b_1,...,b_r)</math> is a tuple that [[spanning set|spans]] <math>V</math>, then <math>n\leq r</math>.<ref>S. Axler, "Linear Algebra Done Right," Springer, 2000.</ref> The argument is as follows:
 
Since <math>B_0</math> spans <math>V</math>, the tuple <math>(a_1,b_1,\dots,b_r)</math> also spans. Since <math>a_1\neq 0</math> (because <math>A</math> is linearly independent), there is at least one <math>t \in \{1,\ldots,r\}</math> such that <math>b_{t}</math> can be written as a linear combination of <math>B_1 = (a_1,b_1,\dots,b_{t-1}, b_{t+1}, ... b_r)</math>.  Thus, <math>B_1</math> is a [[spanning set|spanning tuple]], and its length is the same as <math>B_0</math>'s.
 
Repeat this process.  Because <math>A</math> is linearly independent, we can always remove an element from the list <math>B_i</math> which is not one of the <math>a_j</math>'s that we prepended to the list in a prior step (because <math>A</math> is linearly independent, and so there must be some nonzero coefficient in front of one of the <math>b_i</math>'s). Thus, after <math>n</math> iterations, the result will be a tuple <math>B_n = (a_1, \ldots, a_n, b_{m_1}, \ldots, b_{m_k})</math> (possibly with <math>k=0</math>) of length <math>r</math>.  In particular, <math>A \subseteq B_n</math>, so <math>|A| \leq |B_n|</math>, i.e., <math>n \leq r</math>.
 
To prove the finite case of the dimension theorem from this, suppose that <math>V</math> is a vector space and <math>S = \{v_1, \ldots, v_n\}</math> and <math>T = \{w_1, \ldots, w_m\}</math> are both bases of <math>V</math>. Since <math>S</math> is linearly independent and <math>T</math> spans, we can apply Theorem 1 to get <math>m \geq n</math>. And since <math>T</math> is linearly independent and <math>S</math> spans, we get <math>n \geq m</math>. From these, we get <math>m=n</math>.
 
==Kernel extension theorem for vector spaces==
This application of the dimension theorem is sometimes itself called the ''dimension theorem''. Let
 
:''T'': ''U'' → ''V''
 
be a [[linear transformation]]. Then
 
:''dim''(''range''(''T'')) + ''dim''(''kernel''(''T'')) = ''dim''(''U''),
 
that is, the dimension of ''U'' is equal to the dimension of the transformation's [[Range (mathematics)|range]] plus the dimension of the [[Kernel (algebra)|kernel]]. See [[rank-nullity theorem]] for a fuller discussion.
 
==References==
<references />
 
{{DEFAULTSORT:Dimension Theorem For Vector Spaces}}
[[Category:Theorems in abstract algebra]]
[[Category:Theorems in linear algebra]]
[[Category:Articles containing proofs]]

Latest revision as of 10:15, 9 January 2015

Gabrielle is what her hubby loves to call a though she doesn't genuinely like being called of that ranking. As a woman what she really likes is mah jongg but she hasn't ever made a dime by using it. Software developing is where her primary income comes from but nevertheless , soon her husband and consequently her will start their personal own business. For a while she's not long ago in Massachusetts. Go to her website to pick out more: http://circuspartypanama.com/

Feel free to visit my web site clash of clans hack no survey no jailbreak